Saturday, February 08, 2025

Is Elon Musk America's Dictator? We Will Soon Know.

According to the Oxford English Dictionary, a "dictator" is "an absolute ruler of a state, esp. one whose rule displaces that of a democratic government."  In the United States, the American democratic government is delineated in the Constitution and in the laws of Congress as the supreme lawmaking body elected by the people, with the President charged to "take Care that the Laws be faithfully executed," and with the Courts ensuring that the Constitution, the laws of the United States, and all treaties shall be "the supreme Law of the Land."  The fundamental principle is the rule of law, such that no one is above or outside the law.  Therefore, an American dictator would be an absolute ruler who would displace this democratic rule of law.

In my previous post, I suggested that Donald Trump and Elon Musk have emerged in the first few weeks of Trump's term as wanting to become dictators.  It now appears that we will know for sure whether that is the case within the next week.

I say that because of what happened early this morning (February 8).  Acting on orders from Trump, Musk has gained access to the Treasury Department's payment and data systems.  This system channels about 90 percent of the payments for the U.S. government (about $6.75 trillion last fiscal year)--the funds paid directly to people in the states as well as state governments.  This includes, for example, Social Security benefits, veteran's benefits, and federal employee wages.  This money has already been allocated by Congress.  But Trump wants Musk to be able to cut those federal payments if he so chooses.  Moreover, Musk's access to the Treasury Department's systems gives him access to all of Americans' private information stored in those systems.

On the evening of February 7th, the Attorneys General of 19 States filed an application with the U.S. District Court for the Southern District of New York asking for a temporary restraining order that would deny Musk's access to the Treasury Department's systems.  This morning, District Judge Paul Engelmayer ruled in their favor.

In his order, Judge Engelmayer agreed with the States that they had four persuasive reasons for why Musk's actions were illegal and unconstitutional.  First, Musk is violating the Administrative Procedure Act, which is the fundamental legislation governing federal administrative procedures.  Second, Musk's actions exceed the statutory authority of the Department of the Treasury.  Third, this violates the separation of powers doctrine.  And, finally, this violates the Take Care Clause of the U.S. Constitution.

Judge Engelmayer issued four orders.  First, the defendants must appear in federal court on February 14 to show cause why an order should not be issued to stop Musk's actions at the Treasury Department.  Second, pending that hearing, Musk and the people acting for him are denied any access to the Treasury Department's systems, and they must "immediately destroy any and all copies of material downloaded from the Treasury Department's records and systems, if any."  Third, defendants must file any opposition submission, and the States must file any reply before the February 14 hearing.  Finally, this order must be filed upon the defendants by 12 noon today (February 8).

I lay out these details to show how this sets up a clear confrontation between the court and Musk.  If he accepts this temporary restraining order, then he has accepted the constraints of the rule of law--at least for now--and he is not a dictator.  But if he and Trump refuse to obey this order, then they have declared themselves America's dictators.

This has broad implications as to whether we are witnessing a full display of a chimpanzee politics of dictatorship by Trump and Musk, which I will consider in future posts.  I also need to respond to the "unitary executive" theory of the presidency, which is the interpretation of Article II of the Constitution that supports what Trump is doing.  Trump pointed to this theory in 2019 when he said: "I have an Article II, where I have the right to do whatever I want as president."

Wednesday, February 05, 2025

Elon Musk's Takeover of the U.S. Government Fulfills Curtis Yarvin's MAGA Fascism

Over the past two months, I have argued that the victory of Trump's MAGA movement is Janus-faced.  The liberal face of the movement is manifest in the multiracial and multiethnic coalition of Trump voters and in the liberal pluralism of Trump's Inaugural Address.  But the illiberal face of the movement was displayed at the inauguration by the prominence of the billionaires seated behind Trump, which suggested that Trump might be headed towards Curtis Yarvin's fascism of dictatorial rule by a multibillionaire CEO.

Now, in the first two weeks of Trump's presidency, we have seen that the illiberal face of Yarvin's fascism has prevailed, and it's the face of Elon Musk taking over the U.S. Government, which is exactly the multibillionaire oligarchy proposed by Yarvin.  (Doesn't Musk look like the perfect James Bond villain--the world's richest man who wants to take over the Earth and then Mars?  Where's James Bond when we need him most?)

Whether this exercise of fascist power can be stopped will depend upon the actions of the Congress, the courts, and the military.  The Constitution gives the Congress all the power necessary to check the exercise of arbitrary absolute power by the President and those working for him.  But there's no evidence that the congressional Republicans loyal to Trump and Musk are willing to check their assertion of dictatorial power.  

If the Republicans were to lose control of the Congress in the mid-term elections of 2026, the new Congress might try to impeach Trump again.  But in that case, Trump and Musk would overturn the elections by asserting that they were rigged, and they could call out the MAGA militias for another insurrection.

It is also possible that Trump and Musk would declare in 2026 that since the nation is in a permanent state of emergency, elections cannot be held.

The courts can declare the actions of Trump and Musk illegal and unconstitutional.  In fact, they have already violated dozens of laws.  Every time they take over or shut down a federal agency, they are violating the congressional laws that set up and regulate those agencies.  

The Supreme Court could say that Trump and Musk are in violation of the Constitution.  But as I have indicated, the Supreme Court justices loyal to Trump have already ruled--against the original meaning of the Constitution--that the President is a "King Above the Law."  

And even if the Supreme Court were to rule against Trump and Musk, they could simply ignore their ruling.  Indeed, it's likely that Trump and Musk will soon tell their Department of Justice to refuse to obey any court orders that restrict presidential rule by executive decrees.  (The intellectual impetus for what Trump and Musk are doing comes from scholars who argue for a "unitary presidency," which allows for the president to exercise arbitrary and absolute powers during times of emergency.  Much of this reasoning comes from Carl Schmitt, the legal apologist for the Nazis who insisted that the "Leader Principle" transcended the law.)

As I have suggested in the past, when Trump lost the election in 2020, some of the people around him urged him to call out the military to overturn the election, but he was warned by General Mark Milley and others that the military would not obey.  But now, we see that in planting his loyalists in the Defense Department, he could be preparing the military to support his fascist rule.  (Notice that Trump's Defense Department has revoked General Milley's security detail, which exposes him to assassination by one of Trump's militia men.)

So, it all comes down to one question.  Will the military obey the commands of Trump and Musk in support of a fascist oligarchy?  

Whether a dictator has a minimal winning coalition often depends on whether he has sufficient support in the military.

And so we see the end of America's experiment in liberal democracy coming on the eve of the 250th anniversary of the Declaration of Independence in 2026.

Friday, January 24, 2025

Trump's "Manifest Destiny" for Americans on Mars. Great Idea--If Only Those American Martians Weren't Likely to Die in Space!

One of the most interesting passages in Donald Trump's Second Inaugural Address was his expansion of America's "manifest destiny" to include not only conquering the Panama Canal, the Gulf of America, Canada, and Greenland, but also colonizing Mars.  This passage comes near the end of the speech:

The United States will once again consider itself a growing nation--one that increases our wealth, expands our territory, builds our cities, raises our expectations, and carries our flag into new and beautiful horizons.

And we will pursue our manifest destiny into the stars, launching American astronauts to plant the Stars and Stripes on the planet Mars.

Ambition is the lifeblood of a great nation, and, right now, our nation is more ambitious than any other.  There's no nation like our nation.

Americans are explorers, builders, innovators, entrepreneurs, and pioneers.  The spirit of the frontier is written into our hearts.  The call of the next great adventure resounds from within our souls.

Our American ancestors turned a small group of colonies on the edge of a vast continent into a mighty republic of the most extraordinary citizens on Earth.  No one comes close.

Americans pushed thousands of miles through rugged land of untamed wilderness. . . .

Anyone who knows anything about Elon Musk and his SpaceX will immediately recognize that Trump here was reading language suggested by Musk.  Indeed, those watching Trump read this part of the speech saw Musk cheering this part of the speech.

In recent years, I have written as many as ten posts on the possibility of colonizing Mars, and I have pointed out the many problems with such a project.  I see no evidence that either Trump or anyone else in the White House has thought about these problems, with the exception of Musk.  If you go to the White House website, and search for "Mars," you will be directed to the Inaugural Address, but nothing else.  Since most of Trump's policies are coming from the Heritage Foundation's "Project 2025," you might think his proposal for colonizing Mars is there.  But if you search the "Project 2025" text (almost 1,000 pages) for "Mars," nothing comes up.  

In the 1960s, NASA had planned to extend the Apollo Program, so that after landing on the Moon in 1969, we could go on to land on Mars in the 1980s.  Those plans were thrown out during the Nixon Administration.  

But then, in 1996, Robert Zubrin published his book The Case for Mars.  The book was so successful that it created a popular fascination with Zubrin's plans for travelling to and settling Mars.  Zubrin founded The Mars Society in 1998 to promote his ideas.  

Elon Musk read The Case for Mars, and he was persuaded by Zubrin's argument.  As one of the cofounders of PayPal, Musk was on his way to becoming a multibillionaire; and he was looking for ambitious new projects.  In 2001, he met Zubrin, and he began contributing to the Mars Society.  Following Zubrin's advice, Musk set up SpaceX in 2002, which became the most amazing aerospace company, doing things that NASA thought impossible. 

Today, SpaceX has over 6,000 Starlink satellites in low-Earth orbit, providing satellite internet service to over 70 countries.  SpaceX launches hundreds of new satellites into orbit every year. 

In recent years, SpaceX has been testing Starship, the biggest and most powerful space rocket ever built.  Musk predicts that an uncrewed Starship will test land on Mars in 3 to 4 years.  Then, Starship will begin taking people to Mars and establishing permanent settlements on the planet within the next two decades.

Is this a good idea?  In my posts, I have tried to answer that question by considering both the case for Mars (best stated by Zubrin and the astrobiologist Charles Cockell) and the case against Mars (best stated by Kelly and Zach Weinersmith).  There are some easy problems and some hard problems.


THE EASY PROBLEMS

The easy problems are the technological problems with developing space rockets that could transport lots of cargo, including lots of human beings, to and from Mars in such a way as to establish and sustain a large Mars colony of thousands or perhaps a million human beings.  NASA has already sent landers and rovers to Mars that are exploring the planet and sending back information.  But this is very expensive--as measured by dollars per pound of cargo--and the main reason for the great expense is that the rockets delivering payloads into space are not reusable.  It would be like a Boeing 747 airliner that could be used for only one flight.  No one could afford the airline tickets.

Musk's SpaceX has been solving this problem by building rockets that are reusable, so that the expense per pound of cargo drops dramatically.  When Starship is fully operational, both the Starship and its SuperHeavy Booster will return to their base after launch so that they can be launched again.  Trump has talked about how exciting it was to see the SuperHeavy Booster return to base for the first time.


THE HARD PROBLEMS

And then there are the really hard problems.  The first one is that the universe wants to kill us.  The universe does not seem to be hospitable to life--particularly, human intelligent life.  We have not found life anywhere beyond the Earth.  And even on the Earth, we know that the Earth has been lifeless for most of its history.  The conditions in the Earth's biosphere for sustaining human life have arisen only for a few million years.  

And once we leave the Earth's biosphere, the lack of a breathable atmosphere, food, water, and protection from deadly cosmic radiation make the extraterrestrial universe a constant threat to human life.  As I have indicated in my previous posts, no one knows how to create an artificial biosphere in deep space that would sustain human life for prolonged periods.

The second hard problem is that the analogy of Mars as the "new frontier" is dubious.  Zubrin and Musk have promoted this analogy, which is assumed in Trump's speech.  Just as "Americans pushed thousands of miles through a rugged land of untamed wilderness" in the American West, Trump proclaims, now Americans will push to explore and settle the wilderness of Mars.

The problem with this analogy, as the Weinersmiths have argued, is that it's a false analogy in that while the American settlers in the West were moving through the biosphere of the Earth, the American Martians will have to enter the "necrosphere" of Mars where "the ground is poison, there is no air, and cascades of radiation are fired at the inhabitants on a perpetual basis."

Zubrin's analogy between America and Mars could become a true analogy once we learn how to artificially recreate the Earth's biosphere on Mars--perhaps by terraforming Mars.  The Weinersmiths think that's a possibility that we should strive for, but it will require a century or more of research and development: it would be wise to wait and then go big.  

People like Musk and Zubrin will have to persuade us that waiting is foolish and that it would be wise for us to go now.

The third hard problem is the problem of liberty on Mars.  This is a problem because of what Cockell calls "the problem of oxygen":  the concentration of power in a centralized Martian government ("Muskow"?) that controls the artificial life support systems that provide oxygen and other resources necessary for life will exercise absolute power over the people, whose obedience will be enforced by the threat of withdrawing their life support.

Cockell has argued that Mars could be "engineered for liberty" by devising a Martian system of limited government with checks and balances that would secure individual rights--something like the Lockean liberal democracy of America.  But it's not clear whether that would work on Mars.

Zubrin has argued, however, that the only successful human settlements in space will have to be inclined towards liberty.  He sees two reasons for this.  The first reason is that any successful extraterrestrial society will have to respect individual liberty because only free people with freedom of thought and action can provide the inventive innovation that creates and sustains the technology of artificial life support required for extraterrestrial environments.

The second reason is that only free societies will attract immigrants, and Martian societies will need immigrants to overcome their severe labor shortage.  "From a Darwinian point of view," Zubrin insists, "an extraterrestrial tyranny is an impossibility because that colony would not be able to grow, it would not be able to blossom.  It would be outcompeted for immigrants by ones that offer greater liberty."

I see this as an extension to Mars of Lockean liberal symbolic niche construction and the evolution of cultural group selection with a Lockean open borders policy.

But this assumes that we could figure out how to create a Lockean liberal society within an artificial biosphere on Mars.

The fourth hard problem is the most profound one--the problem of figuring out the meaning of our place in the universe.  Will travel in deep space constantly remind us that the whole universe wants to kill us?  And if that is so, does that teach us that the universe does not care for or about us?  Or can human beings find their purpose inherent in human life itself--in pursuing their natural human desires as shaped in the environment of evolutionary adaptation on the Earth--even though human life is only a momentary emergence in the history of a cosmos that has no eternal purpose?

Or will exploring and colonizing deep space induce a sense of awe before the mysteries of the cosmos that suggests some divine or transcendent cause of the cosmos?


LET THE PEOPLE DECIDE FOR THEMSELVES?

If we agree with the Declaration of Independence that human beings have a natural right to consent to a government to secure their rights to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness, then we can foresee that people settling on Mars will want to establish such a government.  But will they succeed in doing that?

Kelly and Zach Weinersmith, Robert Zubrin, and Charles Cockell give us a wide range of answers to that question.  The Weinersmiths say no:  this cannot be done, at least not within the next 100 years, because we don't know how to keep people alive on Mars, and we're not going to be securing their liberty or their pursuit of happiness if they're dead.  That's why Mars sucks.

Although Cockell agrees with the Weinersmiths that Mars sucks, he believes we can develop the technology for securing at least the minimal conditions for some people to live on Mars.  Since Mars is so awful, however, he foresees that few people will want to live there.  He thinks a few adventurous scientists (like himself) will go there to study Mars in searching for answers about the origins, development, and diversity of life in the universe.  And yet, even these few scientists will not want to stay on Mars for long.

If the Weinersmiths are right, this won't happen anytime soon because the death rate for these Mars-bound scientists will be so great that most scientists will decide it's not worth the risk.

But even if the Weinersmiths are wrong, so that eventually a large number of people go to Mars to establish permanent settlements, Cockell worries that their governments on Mars will tend to be tyrannical because of the "problem of oxygen":  the concentration of power in a centralized government that controls the artificial life support systems that provide oxygen and other resources necessary for life will exercise absolute power over the people, whose obedience will be enforced by the threat of withdrawing their life support.

To overcome this tendency to Martian tyranny, Cockell insists that we will need to design economic, social, and political institutions that limit, divide, and decentralize power to protect liberty; and in doing that, we can draw lessons from the liberal institutions for promoting liberty on Earth, particularly in the history of the United States.

Zubrin insists that the Weinersmiths refuse to take seriously the ways in which the technology of supporting life in space can reduce the risks to human life that come from space travel and living on a planet like Mars.

And just as the Weinersmiths exaggerate the threats to life in space, Zubrin argues, Cockell exaggerates the threats to liberty.  Actually, Zubrin claims, "the case for Mars is liberty."  "Whether they wish to or not, Martian cities will compete for immigrants.  The ones with the best ideas will draw the most people.  This is why dystopian totalitarian space colonies controlled by villains who tyrannize their subjects by threatening to cut off their air will remain mere fictions.  A successful extraterrestrial tyranny is impossible because no one would move there" (Zubrin 2024: 11-12, 187).

On Mars, Zubrin argues, there will be a Darwinian cultural evolution by natural selection that favors liberty.  "The evolution of Martian cities, like that of biological species on Earth, will be governed by natural selection.  The cities that attract the most immigrants will grow" (Zubrin 2024: 12-13, 152).  And those cities that attract the most immigrants will be those that secure liberty--the liberty that fosters the innovative inventiveness in technology necessary for human surviving and thriving on Mars.

Although Zubrin does not cite Locke, he is restating Locke's argument for immigration as cultural group selection that favors free societies.

I don't know how to resolve this debate.  But then perhaps we don't need to.  Ultimately, people will decide this for themselves.

Now that Elon Musk and other space entrepreneurs have shown that it's possible and even likely that privately organized space travel with little or no dependence on governmental space agencies can send a crewed spaceship to land on Mars in ten or twenty years, we can expect that this is going to happen.  Then people will decide whether to go to Mars or not.

If Mars really is as awful as the Weinersmiths and Cockell say it is, then Cockell is probably right in predicting that only a few scientists and professional astronauts will be willing to go.  They will voluntarily agree to face the dangers of space.  And as they spend years in space travel and on the surface of Mars, they will provide the best test of whether life and liberty on Mars is possible.  Over the years, people will learn from their experience and decide whether it's worth going.

As long as this is all voluntary and based on informed consent, I don't see anything wrong with it.

Now, I know that the Weinersmiths have warned that we know very little about the possibility of "space babies": we don't know whether people in space will be able to safely reproduce and rear their young without damaging effects from space on the children.  And surely even if the adults have voluntarily assumed the risks of space travel, the fetuses and the children will not have consented to this.

But don't we rightly allow people a lot of freedom in trying out experimental reproductive technology--in vitro fertilization for example?  This imposes a risk on the offspring to which the offspring cannot consent.  Would this also apply to reproduction in space or on Mars as risky experimentation chosen by the parents?

The Weinersmiths say that before we do this, we should experiment with sending mice, or preferably primate animals, into space to see if they can safely reproduce offspring that can grow to healthy adulthood.

I can see the argument for doing that.  But I can also see that if we allow men and women to voluntarily go to Mars, they will eventually engage in their own sexual and reproductive experiments in space.

I can also imagine that if people are free to decide whether to go to Mars, they will decide what this means for their place in the universe.  Some people might decide that human beings were created by God live on the Earth until they die, and only in the afterlife will they achieve an extraterrestrial eternal life of happiness in Heaven or torment in Hell.  Others might decide that going to Mars is a way of exploring the mystery of the Universe that God has created for us: these colonists on Mars will want to satisfy their natural desires for spiritual transcendence and religious understanding.

Others will feel no need to find a sacred meaning to the universe because they will be satisfied to explore that universe for the pleasure of understanding it, and even if they decide human travel in deep space is too dangerous right now, they will be happy to explore the deepest reaches of the universe through telescopes, unmanned spacecraft, and robotic explorers.  

These philosophic explorers can still hope to solve the problem of how human beings can travel in extraterrestrial space for prolonged periods without suffering disabling and deadly damage to their bodies and brains.  They might consider at least three ways to solve this problem.  We could bioengineer human beings to be better adapted for living in space.  Or we could overcome the physiological limitations of the human body by replacing some biological organs and limbs with mechanical or electronic parts to create cyborgs that could live well in space.  Or we could create superhuman entities with artificial intelligence designed for life in space.  But then we might wonder whether this is technologically possible.  And if it is possible, could this engineering include engineering these beings for liberty?  Or would these bioengineered, cybernetic, or transhuman entities be inclined to tyranny?

I see no indications that Trump and his people have thought about these questions.  But the rest of us should.

Thursday, January 23, 2025

The Illiberalism of the MAGA Intellectual: Curtis Yarvin's "Confederate Racist Fascism."

Meta CEO Mark Zuckerberg, Amazon CEO Jeff Bezos, Google CEO Sundar Pichai, Tesla and SpaceX CEO Elon Musk, Apple CEO Tim Cook, and TikTok CEO Shou Zi Chew.  

Why did Donald Trump place these tech CEOs--some of the richest human beings in the world--in the front row immediately behind him at his inauguration, while the most prominent elected Republican leaders were forced to sit in the back row, hidden from view?

One possible answer is that this shows the influence of the MAGA intellectual Curtis Yarvin, who argues that the only escape from the obvious failures of liberal democracy is to establish an American feudal autocracy ruled by tech CEOs.  A few days ago, the New York Times published an interview of Yarvin where he briefly stated some of his ideas.  What he says here is vague and incoherent, but he is clear about his hope that tech CEOs will take over monarchic control of America under Trump's Caesaristic leadership.

A better exposition of Yarvin's thinking comes in his extensive internet writing over the past twenty years, which I have analyzed in a series of posts a few years ago.  Here I will briefly summarize some of my main points.

I had never heard of Curtis Yarvin until I saw that the Claremont Institute was publishing some of his writing.  Once I began looking at his work, I knew that something strange was happening at the Claremont Institute.  

Yarvin ridicules the Declaration of Independence, scorns the American Revolution as "thuggery, treason, and hypocrisy," and takes the side of the Loyalists in their defense of King George III's monarchic rule over America.  He also praises the Confederacy for fighting a war of secession to defend slavery, which he regards as "a natural human relationship."  The only mistake the Confederates made, Yarvin believes, is that they did not see themselves as reactionary Cavaliers trying to restore the Stuart monarchy.  Yarvin says that he likes to "flirt" with "Confederate racist fascism."

I think I know what Harry Jaffa would have said about this.  Is this what the Claremont Institute now stands for?

I have said that Yarvin is intellectually stimulating because he is one of the few--maybe the only one--of the Anglo-American Far Right thinkers today willing to be truly reactionary by rooting far-right thinking in the Tory ideology of divine-right monarchy and Robert Filmer's Patriarcha in opposition to the Whig Lockean ideology of natural rights to equal liberty and government by the consent of the governed.

But still there are two big problems in his remarkably weak arguments.  First, his favorite form of argumentation is begging the question: he finds a writer who agrees with him, he paraphrases or quotes from that writer, and he then he concludes: ah, you see, I must be right because this writer agrees with me!  I have seen the same kind of sophistical rhetoric in the work of other critics of liberalism, such as Patrick Deneen and Rod Dreher.

The second problem with Yarvin's rhetorical style of arguing is that he does not survey the relevant empirical evidence for deciding the historical disputes that he enters.  So if he wants to prove that modern liberal democracy inevitably leads to disorder, while archaic autocratic authoritarianism leads to order, he needs to present the empirical evidence for that, which he rarely does.

An example of the first problem is Yarvin's attack on the Declaration of Independence.  He calls as his "first witness"--Thomas Hutchinson, a leading Loyalist.  He allows Hutchinson to speak through his 1776 pamphlet Strictures upon the Declaration of the Congress at Philadelphia--a Loyalist attack on the Declaration of Independence.  He calls other witnesses, but they are all Loyalists.  He does this even though he says that "there is no such thing as a neutral primary source," which leads us to expect that he will introduce primary sources on both sides of the debate, but he never does.

Even in his exposition of Hutchinson's Strictures, Yarvin does not tell his readers that a dozen or more scholars studying the Declaration of Independence have critically responded to Hutchinson's pamphlet.  For example, Hans Eicholz has done this in his book Harmonizing Sentiments: The Declaration of Independence and the Jeffersonian Idea of Self-Government (New York: Peter Lang, 2001), which includes a reprint of Hutchinson's whole pamphlet.

An example of the second problem with Yarvin's rhetoric--failing to survey the relevant empirical evidence--is his prediction that feudal illiberal societies will have low rates of violent crime, while modern liberal societies will have high rates.  In making this argument, he is silent about the quantitative historical evidence that from high rates of violence and homicide in the Middle Ages, there has been a long decline in modern liberal societies, which shows that liberalism promotes moral self-command, and that peop0le in pre-modern illiberal societies suffered from a lack of self-control.

Another example is his claim that "slavery is a natural human relationship."  He says that most slave masters have been benevolent in their treatment of their slaves.  He dismisses the depiction of the brutality of slavery in Harriot Beecher Stowe's Uncle Tom's Cabin as "propaganda."  But he is silent about the factual evidence for the brutality of slavery that Stowe presented to show that her novel was not just "propaganda."  She published a book--A Key to Uncle Tom's Cabin: Original Facts and Documents--in which she provided extensive documentation to confirm her claim that the fictional story of her novel was an accurate depiction of what American slavery was like.  Now, maybe Yarvin would want to say that her evidence is not persuasive, but he would have to argue for that, which he has not done, because he never wants the burden of responding to possible criticisms of what he says.

I draw two conclusions from all of this.  Yarvin is not a serious thinker.  And if Trump and his people decide to embrace his "Confederate racist fascism" ruled by tech CEO billionaires, they will destroy the liberal pluralist coalition that voted for Trump in November.

The Liberalism of Trump's Second Inaugural Address

Detroit Pastor Lorenzo Sewell's Prayer at President Trump's Second Inauguration



Leading up to the presidential election, scholarly commentators like Robert Kagan and Steven Hahn claimed that if Donald Trump were elected, this would show the triumph of the illiberal tradition of American politics in defeating the American liberal tradition.  

As I indicated in a post last November, I agree with Kagan and Hahn that the political history of America has been a continuing battle between liberalism and illiberalism.  But I think the liberal tradition of American political thought--as expressed in the opening paragraphs of the Declaration of Independence--has ultimately prevailed over the illiberal tradition.  And I see that even in the MAGA movement.  I agree that much of Trump's rhetoric has illiberal, and even fascist, overtones.  But most of the MAGA voters accept the liberal principles of the Declaration of Independence.  (I have written previously about the prominence of the Declaration of Independence in the rhetoric of the 2020 Republican National Convention.)

Here I use the term "liberalism" in the broad Lockean sense that includes both those who we call "liberals" in America and those we call "conservatives"--as opposed to the illiberal Left (such as the socialists), on the one extreme, and the illiberal Right (such as the reactionaries and fascists), on the other extreme. 

We can see the triumph of the American liberal tradition in Trump's election.  The American illiberal tradition defends the national racial, religious, and ethnic homogeneity of a white Anglo-Saxon Protestant America against subversion by both internal and external enemies.  (Consider the Ku Klux Klan of the 1920s, for example.)  But Trump's electoral victory depended on a pluralistic coalition of voters who were racially, ethnically, and religiously diverse.  As opposed to a WASPish illiberal America, it was a culturally heterogeneous liberal America that voted for Trump.  If Trump's presidency gives into his illiberal propensities, he will alienate these MAGA voters.

If Trump appealed only to illiberal voters like the proponents of Christian theocracy and the white racists, he would never win any election.  Given the religious, racial, and ethnic pluralism of the American electorate, Trump can win only with the support of a multireligious, multiracial, and multiethnic coalition that includes Protestants, Catholics, Jews, and most of the white working-class voters with large portions of the Hispanic, Asian, and black voters.  The evidence for that became clear in the 2020 election, as compared with the 2016 election, in which Trump's vote share in each of these groups trended in his favor.  That trend continued in the 2024 election. 

As I have argued previously, Trump's chimpanzee politics requires a minimum winning coalition.  Trump paid tribute to the liberal pluralism of his winning electoral coalition in the ceremony and the speech for his second inauguration.  But he also showed the illiberal face of MAGA by filling the front row seats behind him with tech CEO billionaires, which was a symbolic display of the illiberal thinking of MAGA intellectuals like Curtis Yarvin (more about that in the next post).

In his Inaugural Address, Trump proclaimed that having been miraculously saved from assassination, "I was saved by God to make America great again."  This echoes the illiberal message of the MAGA theocrats that Trump has been chosen by God as His Cyrus to save America.  But in saying that "we will not forget our God," Trump was careful to suggest that this was an ecumenical God, and therefore he did not establish any particular religious tradition as America's church.  In this way, he favored the liberal tradition of Roger Williams over the illiberal tradition of John Winthrop.

Trump's endorsement of religious pluralism was clear in his selection of clergy to deliver the opening and closing prayers--two Catholics (Cardinal Timothy Dolan and the Reverend Frank Mann), two Protestants (Franklin Graham and Lorenzo Sewell), and one Jew (Rabbi Ari Berman).  Remarkably, the first printed program for the inauguration included a Muslin cleric--Imam Husham Al-Husainy, a prominent Muslim leader in Dearborn, Michigan, who had endorsed Trump and thus helped Trump win the Muslim votes that he needed to win Michigan.  This would have been the first time in history for a Muslim cleric to appear at a presidential inauguration. There was no public explanation for why Al-Husainy was dropped from the program, but there were some newspaper reports from Michigan that Trump's pro-Israel supporters objected that Al-Husainy was sympathetic to Iran and Hezbollah.

Although the Trump voters include Protestant theocrats and Catholic integralists, the liberal religious pluralism of Trump's inauguration gave no encouragement to either group.

By endorsing such a broadly ecumenical religious pluralism, Trump was following the example set by the coronation of King Charles III two years ago, in which the monarchic head of the Church of England displayed his Lockean liberalism by allowing all religious faiths to be represented.

Moreover, one of the dramatic high points of the inaugural ceremony was Lorenzo Sewell's prayer, which was actually an abbreviated rendition of Martin Luther King's "I Have a Dream" speech, which was appropriate since January 20th was Martin Luther King Day.  Sewell emphasized King's appeal to the Lockean liberalism of the Declaration of Independence, particularly in its principle that "all men are created equal."

King's "Dream" was that America would finally fulfill the principles of the Declaration of Independence.  Trump stressed this explicitly in his speech: "Today is Martin Luther King Day.  And his honor--this will be a great honor.  But in his honor, we will strive together to make his dream a reality.  We will make his dream come true." 

In support of this promise, Trump pointed to the racial and ethnic pluralism of his winning coalition:

"As our victory showed, the entire nation is rapidly unifying around our agenda with dramatic increases in support from virtually every element of our society: young and old, men and women, African Americans, Hispanic Americans, Asian Americans, urban, suburban, rural.  And very importantly, we had a powerful win in all seven swing states, and the popular vote, we won by millions of people."

"To the Black and Hispanic communities, I want to thank you for the tremendous outpouring of love and trust that you have shown me with your vote.  We set records, and I will not forget it.  I've heard your voices in the campaign, and I look forward to working with you in the years to come."

And yet any careful viewer of Trump's inauguration should have noticed that it was Janus-faced.  The liberal face was the invocation of King's "Dream" of equal liberty for all racial, ethnic, and religious groups.  The illiberal face was the prominent front row audience immediately behind Trump--with the seats filled by a half dozen tech CEO billionaires who are the richest human beings on the Earth.  If Trump meant this to suggest that these are to become the new oligarchic rulers of America, then he's showing the influence of the illiberal fascist Curtis Yarvin.

Thursday, January 16, 2025

American Indian Tribes in the Evolution of a Multiethnic American Nation

Despite the claim of the theorists of settler colonialism that the European colonialization of North America required the genocidal extinction of the Native American Indians, it is remarkable that most if not all of those American Indian Nations that occupied North America in 1492 have survived into twenty-first century America.  More than five hundred Native nations still exist today in the United States.  But since those American Indian Nations lack the independent self-governing sovereignty that defines a "nation," it would be better to identify them as American Indian tribes or ethnicities existing today in a multiethnic American Nation.  (As suggested by the Oxford English Dictionary, I define "tribe" as "a division of some other nation or people" and "ethnicity" as "membership in a group having a common cultural tradition.")

Before 1871, the U.S. Congress recognized the American Indian nations as true nations by making treaties with them.  After 1871, the Congress refused to recognize the American Indian tribes as independent nations with whom the U.S. could make treaties.

Before the arrival of Europeans in America, and for almost four hundred years after their arrival, the American Indians satisfied their evolved natural desire for social membership by living in hundreds of independent sovereign nations (Moffett 2019).  But eventually, once they were defeated in war, they were forced to choose between living on Indian reservations as "dependent domestic nations," as Supreme Court Justice John Marshall called them, or fully assimilating themselves into American society while preserving some social identity as a member of an Indian society (Cherokees, Shawnees, Kiowas, and so on).  This shows what Mark Moffett has identified as "the single most radical innovation in the history of human societies"--a modern society like America can grow by absorbing formerly separate societies that become distinct ethnicities in a multiethnic society (309).  Because of this evolutionary innovation, most nations today, even those that seem homogeneous, are really blended admixtures of originally separate peoples into one people.

The identity of the American people as a people can arise from their dedication to the principles of equality of rights in the Declaration of Independence, which allows for a multiethnic and pluralistic national identity that embraces hundreds of American Indian ethnicities.

In Native Nations: A Millenium in North America, historian Kathleen DuVal has shown how the Indigenous Americans built powerful and diverse nations that controlled the North American continent for thousands of years.  Even after the Europeans arrived, over 90% of the continent was still dominated by the Indigenous Nations, who dictated the terms of their engagement with European traders, explorers, missionaries and diplomats, which allowed the Indians to enjoy the benefits of global networks of economic and cultural exchange.  Prior to the 1820s, no European army had ever been through most of the regions inhabited by the American Indians.  Most of the European settlers were confined to the eastern fringes of the continent along the Atlantic coast.  It was not until the middle of the 19th century (1830 to 1880) that the Indians lost control of most of the continent.  


EVOLUTION BY POPULATION GROWTH

This was due mostly to the massive growth in the European American population in contrast to the small population of the American Indians.  In 1750, the total European population north of central Mexico was probably around one million, which was probably roughly equal to the American Indian population.  But most of the Europeans--about 900,000 were confined to the East Coast.  Across the rest of the continent, the Indigenous people far outnumbered the few Europeans.  But after 1750, the European population began to double every generation--both because their agricultural economy could feed a lot of people and because of immigration.

By 1800, there were less than 100,000 Indians east of the Mississippi, as compared with five million European Americans.  In 1810, the U.S. population had grown to seven million; and in 1820, it was ten million.  The Indian population during this time was growing, but it was still outnumbered by a factor of one hundred to one.  Remarkably, this ratio of one hundred to one is still about the same today.  There are perhaps as many as one million Indians living on reservations, and as many as four to five million claim to be "American Indian" on census forms.  

Most of these people who claim American Indian identity are mixed-race.  This shows the Darwinian evolution of Indigenous Americans through genetic and cultural hybridization, which supports the pluralism of the American Indian Nations living in a Multiethnic American Nation.

This sustains DuVal's general argument in Native Nations that while some European settlers attempted a genocidal extermination of the Native Americans, those attempts failed to extinguish those Native Americans.  It is important to see that the common assumption that the American Indians were helpless victims of European conquest, because they were inevitably doomed to extinction, and unable to offer any resistance to the overwhelming power of the European settlers, is false.  Because it ignores the power of the Indians in dominating the North American continent, at least up to the middle of the 19th century.  This assumption of American Indian helplessness is also false in ignoring the fact that the American Indian resistance to annihilation brought about the survival of the Native American nations.


THE "ORIGINAL NATURAL RIGHTS" OF THE AMERICAN INDIAN NATIONS: THE EVOLUTION OF PROPERTY AS A SYMBOLIC INHERITANCE SYSTEM

But then we might wonder about the legal, and even constitutional, status of those Indigenous Nations within the United States.  Justice John Marshall provided the best answer to that question in a series of three Supreme Court opinions, which confirm what John Locke had said about how conquerors are constrained by the propensity of a conquered people to resist their oppression.

In Johnson v. McIntosh (21 U.S. [8 Wheat.] 543 [1823]), the question was whether Indian nations northwest of the Ohio River, in 1773, and 1775, had a property right to their lands, so that they could sell those lands to American settlers, and whether American courts should recognize those land titles, which would justify an action of ejectment against the holder of a federal land patent for those lands.  To justify his claim that the Courts of the U.S. would have to uphold the federal land patent, Justice Marshall offered a general history of how European governments gained ultimate authority over land titles in America by discovery of the land and conquest of the American Indians.

Marshall began by asserting that it is the right of society to prescribe the rules by which property is acquired and preserved; and therefore, the title to lands must depend entirely on the legal rules of property prescribed by the nation in which those lands lie.  In trying to identify those legal rules, we can look to two kinds of principles.  First, there are those universal "principles of abstract justice, which the Creator of all things has impressed on the mind of his creature man, and which are admitted to regulate, in a great degree, the rights of civilized nations, whose perfect independence is acknowledged."  Second, there are "those principles also which our own government has adopted in the particular case, and given us as the rule for our decision" (572).

Considered in the light of the evolutionary psychology of law, I have argued, we can see that all legal and moral rules are imaginary social realities created by the evolved human capacity for language and symbolism by which we agree with one another to collectively recognize those legal and moral rules.  So, we can collectively agree on what counts as a legitimate claim to property.  

Evolutionary psychology can also explain what Marshall calls "the principles of abstract justice."  To avoid the dangers of both tyrannical dominance and factional conflict, natural selection favored moral judgment as a strategy for choosing sides in conflicts by impartial rules of action.  Moral judgment is the uniquely human capacity of the human mind for creating rules of right and wrong and then applying those rules to conflicts so that people can choose the right side over the wrong side.  If most people do this, and if they share the same rules and evidence, they will choose the same side in conflicts.  The majority of the people in a society can then coordinate their choices through impartial moral rules without following the hierarchy, which checks the power of the dominants, and without strengthening rival factions.  But when there is disagreement--either within or between societies--over these moral rules, the disagreement will have to be settled either by persuasive debate or by coercive force.

So, for example, the most people in all societies agree on the impartial rule of action that "anyone who steals someone else's property shall be punished."  But people can disagree about what should count as "stealing," "property," and "punishment."

Evolutionary psychology can also explain the moral principles of property "which the Creator of all things has impressed on the mind of his creature man" as rooted in the sense of "self-ownership" that natural selection has impressed on the evolved human mind.  If human beings did not have any sense of owning themselves, they could not claim ownership of things external to them as extensions of their self-owning selves.

The American Indians understood their ownership of property as an extension of their self-owning selves.  They distinguished between property that belonged to individuals, families, or households (such as clothing, jewelry, and houses) and property that belonged collectively to their society (such as land, game [before it was killed], and other natural resources) (DuVal 88, 362).

But when conflicts over property arose between Indian nations or between Indians and European settlers or between European colonial governments with conflicting claims, the disputes would have to be resolved either by peaceful negotiation or by violent warfare.

In the history of European colonial claims in America, Marshall saw the doctrine of discovery as the primary principle for resolving disputes over land rights in America.  The European governments agreed that discovery of any American region would give "title to the government by whose subjects, or by whose authority, it was made, against all other European governments, which title might be consummated by possession" (573).  The discoverer then had the exclusive right to acquire land from the native Americans and to regulate the relations between the discoverer and the natives.  Deciding to what extent and in what ways the property rights of the American natives could be recognized was to be ultimately determined by the absolute authority of the discoverer.

For this European principle of discovery, it did not matter that the original discoverers of the Americas were the Native Americans.  Because the land right conferred by discovery was confined to countries "then unknown to all Christian people" (576).  Thus, the Christian Europeans assumed that they had a god-given right to dominate the non-Christian world by conquest.

Remarkably, Marshall admitted that "the title by conquest is acquired and maintained by force," and therefore it is "opposed to natural right" (588-89, 591).

But he also saw that a humanitarian "natural right" as expressed in the natural moral sentiments of public opinion would constrain this title by conquest based on brute force.  "Humanity . . . acting on public opinion" would establish as a general rule "that the conquered shall not be wantonly oppressed."  Popular humanitarianism would demand that the conquered people be "incorporated with the victorious nation, and become subjects or citizens of the government with which they are connected," so that they would become "one people."  Where this happened, "the rights of the conquered to property should remain unimpaired" (589).  Marshall believed that "public opinion, which not even the conqueror can disregard, imposes these restraints upon him; and he cannot neglect them without injury to his fame, and hazard to his power" (590).  In two later Supreme Court decisions, Marshall explained how this might happen. 

Andrew Jackson had long sought to remove the Five Civilized Tribes (Cherokees, Chickasaw, Choctaw, Muscogee [Creek], and Seminoles) from the southeastern region of the United States and force them to move west of the Mississippi to lands that would be designated as "Indian Country."  In 1830, the Congress passed the Indian Removal Act to promote this policy.  But the popular opposition to this policy was so intense that the debate over this law raged for many years.  It was not until 1838 that the forced removal of the Five Civilized Tribes to their Indian territories in what became Oklahoma was carried out.  About 60,000 Indians were removed by military force, and 3,000 to 4,000 of them died during the march west, which became infamous as the "Trail of Tears," and which many people today identify as the clearest case of "genocide" carried out by the U.S. Government.

Shortly after the passage of the Indian Removal Act, the government of the State of Georgia enacted its own laws to abolish the Cherokee Nation as a sovereign nation in northern Georgia.

Under the U.S. Constitution, the Supreme Court has original jurisdiction in any controversy between a State and a foreign nation.  Acting under this provision, in 1830, in Cherokee Nation v. Georgia (30 U.S. [5 Pet.] 1 [1831]), legal representatives of the Cherokee Nation asked the Supreme Court for an injunction to prevent the State of Georgia from enforcing state laws within the Cherokee Nation.  The Cherokee Nation had lived in what is now the southeastern United States for thousands of years.  In 1830, there were as many as 14,000 Cherokees in Georgia living as a sovereign nation on land guaranteed to them by treaties with the U.S. Government.  

But in his majority opinion for the court in Cherokee Nation, Justice Marshall refused to consider the merits of the case because he thought the Cherokees did not have standing to bring the case to the court as a foreign nation.  He insisted that rather than being foreign nations, the Indian nations were "domestic dependent nations."  Their relation to the United States was "a state of pupilage" like "a ward to his guardian" (17).  (Looking back at Marshall's opinion, we can see that this was the first step towards denying that the American Indian tribes were really nations, which is what the Congress did in 1871.)

Marshall thought that the text of the Constitution supported this--particularly, the clause giving Congress the power "to regulate Commerce with foreign Nations, and among the several States, and with the Indian Tribes" (Art. I, sec. 8, cl. 3).  Distinguishing these three distinct classes--foreign nations, the several states, and Indian tribes--must mean that the Indian tribes are not foreign nations.  After all, Marshall observed, the framers of the Constitution could have empowered Congress "to regulate commerce with foreign nations, including the Indian tribes, and among the several states."  By not using this phrasing, the framers clearly intended to deny that the Indian tribes were foreign nations.

Justice Smith Thompson wrote the dissenting opinion in this case (joined by Justice Joseph Story).  His primary argument was that in making treaties with the Indians, the United States government necessarily recognized them as foreign nations, and so there was no reason to read the phraseology of the Commerce Clause as implicitly denying their status as foreign nations.

Moreover, Justice Thompson made it clear that considering the merits of the case should support the claim that the state of Georgia could not legally deny the sovereign authority of the Cherokee Nation.  Thompson cited Emer de Vattel's The Law of Nations (1758) as showing how the Cherokees had all the natural rights that belonged to them as a sovereign nation according to the law of nature.  "Nations being composed of men naturally free and independent, and who, before the establishment of civil societies, live together in the state of nature, nations or sovereign states are to be considered as so many free persons, living together in a state of nature. . . . Every nation that governs itself, under what form soever, without any dependence on a foreign power, is a sovereign state" (53).  

As I have argued previously, Vattel was restating the Lockean understanding of international law as rooted in the law of nature in the state of nature, which was also expressed in the Declaration of Independence as part of the Lockean liberal evolution of the American nation as symbolic niche construction.

Thompson also cited Vattel for the idea that even in "unequal alliances" between nations, where a weak state puts itself under the protection of a stronger state, the weak state is still a sovereign and independent nation as long as it has self-governing authority.  This should be true for the Cherokee Nation and the other Indian Nations--as long as being under the protection of the United States as a stronger state does not deprive those nations of their self-governing sovereignty.

Remarkably, only one year later, in the case of Worcester v. Georgia (6 Pet. 515 [1832]), Justice Marshall accepted Thompson's reasoning in writing a majority opinion in favor of the Cherokee Nation with the concurrence of Thompson and Story, who had dissented in the Cherokee Nation case.  Marshall agreed with Thompson in drawing from Vattel the idea that "tributary and feudatory states do not thereby cease to be sovereign and independent states, so long as self government and sovereign and independent authority are left in the administration of the state" (561).  This supported the conclusion that "the Indian nations had always been considered as distinct, independent political communities, retaining their original natural rights, as the undisputed possessors of the soil, from time immemorial" (559).

In effect, this decision in Worcester v. Georgia declared the Indian Removal Act and Jackson's policy of forced removal unconstitutional.  Jackson responded by simply ignoring Marshall's decision.  It was reported by some people that Jackson said: "Justice Marshall has made his decision and now let him enforce it."  Although Jackson probably did not utter those exact words, he did certainly disregard Marshall's decision.

But even if the Worcester decision did not protect the Cherokees from forced removal, it did add to the widespread and intense criticism of the forced removal policy as a violation of the "original natural rights" of the American Indians.  Jeff Fynn-Paul has surveyed this "mass resistance to Jackson's policies" as showing that it is mistaken to evoke the Trail of Tears "as typical of American treatment of the Indians, and as unopposed by U.S. institutions or public opinion" (Not Stolen, 275-92).

Moreover, the Worcester decision did become the landmark Supreme Court decision for a federal Indian policy that recognized the limited sovereignty of the Native American Nations.  That sovereignty was at first limited but then completely denied by the U.S. Congress in its absolute power over the Indian tribes.


THE SURVIVAL OF THE INDIAN ETHNICITIES.  BUT WITHOUT THE "UNRESTRICTED RIGHT OF SELF-GOVERNMENT" THAT BELONGS TO NATIONS

From her history of the native American Indians in North America, Kathleen DuVal draws the conclusion that despite the attempts of European Americans to extinguish them, the American Indian nations have survived:

"Despite the tremendous losses of the past two centuries, Native nations have survived, not only as the descendants of once powerful peoples, but as nations within the nation-states of the United States, Mexico, and Canada.  Since 2000, the U.S. Census has counted more and more Native Americans, with the 2020 census reporting an astounding 9.7 million.  Not all of them are actual citizens of Native nations, but the vast majority do report a specific tribal affiliation, so there is some truth to the number. . . . U.S. policies did unfathomable damage, but Native Americans repeatedly rebuilt their nations and figured out how to continue being their own distinct peoples within a vastly changed continent" (544).

I agree that native American Indians have survived in the United States "as the descendants of once powerful peoples," but I do not agree that they have survived "as nations."  Notice the two problems in her reasoning here.  First, she admits that "not all of them are actual citizens of Native nations."  In fact, most of them reporting "a specific tribal affiliation" are not citizens of any Native nation.  

The second problem is that claiming they have survived "as nations" ignores the fact that in the "law of nations" (international law), and in American constitutional law, a "nation" has the sovereign right of self-government; and if that is what "nation" means, then the American Indian tribes today are not nations, because the U.S. Congress exercises a complete and absolute power over the Indian tribes that denies them any right of self-government.

As I have already suggested, it would be better to say that the American Indians have survived as Indian ethnicities or "distinct peoples" within a multiethnic nation of one American people.

During the first 100 years of American history after the Revolution, the United States government managed relations with the American Indian tribes by making treaties with them, and a treaty is an agreement between nations that are self-governing sovereign states.  Beginning in 1778, when the first treaty was made with the Delawares, the United States government made 370 treaties with the Indian tribes.

But that came to an end in 1871.  In the Indian Appropriations Act of 1871, the Congress declared that the United States would no longer recognize Indian tribes as independent nations with whom the U.S. could make treaties:  "That hereafter no Indian nation or tribe within the territory of the United States shall be acknowledged or recognized as an independent nation, tribe, or power with whom the United States may contract by treaty: Provided, further, that nothing herein contained shall be construed to invalidate or impair the obligation of any treaty heretofore lawfully made and ratified with on such Indian nation or tribe" (16 Stat. 544, 566).

And despite declaring here that treaties previously made with the Indians would be respected, the Congress later claimed the power to abrogate those treaties by statue without the consent of the Indian tribes.

DuVal mentions this 1871 law in two sentences, but she does not reflect on how this denies her claim that the American Indian tribes have survived into the present day as "nations," even though the Congress was very clear in declaring that after 1871 no Indian tribe would be recognized as a nation (495-96).

Amazingly, Pekka Hamalainen--in his recent history of the North American Indians--makes the same mistake as DuVal: he asserts that today the North American continent is "speckled with hundreds of Native nations that preserve Indigenous sovereignty and nationhood" (Hamalainen 2022: 461).  He says nothing about the congressional denial of Indigenous "nationhood" in 1871.  

Actually, the careful reader of Hamalainen's book will notice a confusing ambiguity in his conclusion to this book.  He says that "indigenous sovereignty in North America" lasted for almost 400 years following Columbus's arrival, and it was not until the end of the 19th century that "the United States could claim to have subjugated a critical mass of Native Americans," and so he recognizes that "indigenous sovereignty" was extinguished shortly before 1900.  But then in his last paragraph, he insists that "today, sovereign Indigenous America persists in the dynamism of modern Native communities" (462-63).  The reader is left with a contradiction:  "indigenous sovereignty in North America" does and does not persist today.  (I will have more to say about Hamalainen's book in a future post.)

The constitutionality of the 1871 Act denying Indigenous national sovereignty was upheld by the Supreme Court--it cases such as United States v. Kagama (118 U.S. 375 [1886] and Lone Wolf v. Hitchcock (187 U.S. 553 [1903]--which affirmed that the Congress has "plenary power"--absolute and complete power--over all Native American tribes, which includes the power to abrogate treaties with Indian tribes by federal law.

This plenary power of the Congress over the American Indian tribes has been reaffirmed by the Supreme Court in recent cases.  For example, in the 2020 case McGirt v. Oklahoma (591 U.S. ___ [2020]), Justice Neil Gorsuch, writing for the majority, recognized that by subjecting Indians to federal trials for crimes committed on tribal lands, the Congress had breached its treaty promises that the Indian tribes would be free to govern themselves as sovereign nations.  For example, the Treaty of 1856 with the Creek Indians had promised that the Creeks would be "secured in the unrestricted right of self-government," with "full jurisdiction" over Tribe members and their property.  But since then, the Congress has exercised its plenary power to break its treaty promises to the Tribe.

Notice what this means: the Congress has the tyrannical power to rule over the American Indian tribes without their consent, and thus deny the "self-evident truth" of the Declaration of Independence that "governments are instituted among men, deriving their just powers from the consent of the governed."

Or should we say that although the Congress has deprived the American Indian Nations of their "unrestricted right of self-government," the Congress has granted U.S. citizenship to all American Indians in 1924, which has allowed them the right of self-government as citizens in a multiethnic American Nation?

When the Declaration of Independence in 1776 declared that the "thirteen United States of America" were and of right ought to be "Free and Independent States," the signers knew that the success of this declaration would depend on winning a bloody war of independence and forcing Great Britain to sign a treaty of peace with them, which was achieved with the Treaty of Paris of 1783.

Similarly, the American Indian Nations were "Free and Independent States" for as long as they could go to war with their enemies--other Indian Nations, the European powers, and the Americans--and force their enemies to make treaties with them.  But once they lost their military formidability, they could no longer defend their freedom and independence as sovereign nations, and they became tribes or ethnicities in the American nation.

In the U.S. Army's prolonged war with the American Indians in the 1870s, the Indians won some victories, such as the overwhelming defeat of George Armstrong Custer's soldiers by the Lakotas along the Little Bighorn River in the Black Hills in 1876.  But by 1877, the Indians had lost the war.  When the Nez Perces (living on the Columbia Plateau between the Spokane and Snake Rivers) were defeated in June of 1877, that was the last official military engagement between the United States and North America's Indigenous people (Hamalainen, 448-452).

Locke would say that by 1877 the American Indians had lost their "appeal to Heaven"--the God of Battles had given the victory to the U.S. Army over the Native American warriors.


REFERENCES

DuVal, Kathleen. 2024. Native Nations: A Millennium in North America. New York: Random House.

Fynn-Paul, Jeff. 2023. Not Stolen: The Truth About European Colonialism in the New World. New York: Bombardier Books.

Hamalainen, Pekka. 2022. Indigenous Continent: The Epic Contest for North America. New York: Liveright Publishing.

Moffett, Mark. 2019. The Human Swarm: How Our Societies Arise, Thrive, and Fall. New York: Basic Books.

de Vattel, Emer. 2008 [1758}. The Law of Nations. Edited with an Introduction by Bela Kapossy and Richard Whatmore. Carmel, IN: Liberty Fund.

Saturday, January 04, 2025

The Falsity of Thomas Jefferson's "Prayer for the Nation." Does Mike Johnson's Appeal to Divine Providence Deny the Separation of Church and State?

 

                Mike Johnson's Speech After Being Reelected Speaker of the House of Representatives


Yesterday, Mike Johnson was reelected Speaker of the House of Representatives.  In his acceptance speech, he summarized the major points of Donald Trump's MAGA agenda for the Congress; and in doing that, he insisted that the election of Donald Trump and the new Republican Congress was an act of divine providence.  He explained: "I don't believe in luck or coincidence.  I believe in the idea of providence."  As evidence that the belief in God's providential care for America is part of America's exceptional position in the world, he read what he identified as Thomas Jefferson's "Prayer for America," and he said that Jefferson had said this prayer each day of his eight years as president, and every day thereafter until his death.  In the video above, this comes at around 14 minutes into the speech.  You can also read the text of the speech at Johnson's congressional website.

Johnson identified Jefferson as "the primary author of the Declaration of Independence," in the context of noting that the 250th anniversary of the Declaration of Independence would occur during the term of this 119th Congress in 2026.

Here's the prayer:

Almighty God who has given us this good land for our heritage. We humbly beseech thee that we may always prove ourselves, that people mindful of thy favor and glad to do thy will bless our land with honorable ministry, sound learning and pure manners. Save us from violence, discord and confusion, from pride and arrogance, and from every evil way. Defend our liberties and fashion into one united people, the multitude brought hither out of many kindreds and tongues endow with thy spirit of wisdom, those whom in thy name, we entrust the authority of government. That there may be justice and peace at home, and that through obedience to thy law, we may show forth thy praise among the nations of the Earth. In times of prosperity, fill our hearts with thankfulness and in the day of trouble, suffer not our trust in thee to fail, of which we ask through Jesus Christ our Lord. Amen. 

Johnson then immediately claimed that the election of the Republican Congress was an "act of providence," and that it was "providence that spared President Trump from the assassin's bullet."  In this way, he suggested that God miraculously intervened to save Trump's life so that he could be elected president.  I have written previously about this belief that Trump is God's Chosen One--like God's choice of Cyrus as the Messiah for Israel.

This raises at least two questions.  Is Johnson correct in identifying this as Jefferson's prayer?  And is Johnson's invocation of God's providential care of America compatible with America's fundamental principles?  Or does it contradict the Jeffersonian principle of separating church and state?

The answer to the first question is clearly no.  As indicated by a statement at the website for the Thomas Jefferson Foundation, there is no evidence that this prayer was written by Jefferson.

Moreover, that Jefferson would not have written such a prayer is clear from his refusal as president to proclaim any national day of prayer for the country.  In 1808, Samuel Miller (a minister) sent a letter to Jefferson asking him if he would be receptive to a request from some ministers that he issue a presidential proclamation of a day of "fasting, humiliation, and prayer" before God.  Jefferson replied by saying that he would have to refuse such a request because it would violate the First Amendment's provision that "no law shall be made respecting the establishment, or free exercise, of religion."  He did indicate, however, that since the First Amendment applies only to the national government, a state government might have the right to issue some such proclamation of a national day of prayer.

Apparently, Jefferson believed that a presidential prayer for America like that attributed to him by Johnson would have violated what Jefferson had called the "wall of separation between church and state" in his letter to the Danbury Baptist Association in 1802.  He was responding to a letter from the Danbury Baptists congratulating him on his election in 1800 and endorsing his affirmation of "religious liberty--that religion is at all times and places a matter between God and individuals," and therefore that civil government has no rightful power prescribe religious belief.

As I have indicated in some previous posts, this puts Jefferson on the side of Roger Williams in asserting the "wall of separation" of church and state against the theocracy of John Winthrop.  I have also argued that Jefferson's God in the Declaration of Independence is "Nature's God"--or Spinoza's God who is immanent in the laws of Nature--and this God is not a transcendent God who miraculously intervenes in natural history in answer to prayer.

If this is correct, then Speaker Johnson's political appeal to divine providence violates the American principle of separation of church and state.  It's notable that in his speech, Johnson mentions "seven core principles of America," which are "individual freedom, limited government, the rule of law, peace through strength, fiscal responsibility, free markets, human dignity."  But notice that separation of church and state is not included.

What should Johnson say in his defense?  Unless I am overlooking some documentary evidence for Jefferson's "Prayer for the Nation," Johnson would have to admit that he was wrong about this.

But even if Johnson was wrong about attributing this prayer to Jefferson, Johnson could argue that the religious doctrine of divine providence really is an American political principle.  After all, even if the only reference to God in Jefferson's original draft of the Declaration of Independence was "Nature's God," it is revealing that the revisions of the Declaration coming from others in the Continental Congress added three more references to God--"by their Creator," "appealing to the Supreme Judge of the world," and "with a firm reliance on the Protection of Divine Providence."  

Doesn't this show that America's God is more than just Jefferson's Spinozistic God of Nature--that America's God is a Creator, Judge, and providential Protector of America?

And yet isn't it interesting that we don't see any of this talk about God in the Constitution?  In his speech, Johnson refers to the oath of office prescribed by the Constitution: "we're all going to take an oath--the same one oath, for one nation, and under the banner of one great American flag."  But he is silent about the exact language in the Constitution prescribing this oath: all officers "shall be bound by Oath or Affirmation, to support this Constitution; but no religious Test shall ever be required as a Qualification to any Office or public Trust under the United States" (Article VI).

As I have pointed out, this part of the Constitution has been vehemently criticized by Christians who have said that this allows the offices of government to be filled by "godless" people.  Johnson says nothing about this.

Another problem for Johnson is that he does not explain how he can be so sure that he knows the truth about God and God's will for America.  As I have indicated in a previous post, Johnson is a Young-Earth Creationist who is a follower of Ken Ham, and who therefore believes that God created everything exactly 6,000 years ago, and so the Darwinian science of natural evolution is false and morally degrading.  The fundamental difficulty with this is that he believes that God has revealed this truth to him through the Bible, even though most biblical believers disagree with this.  So, the Holy Spirit has failed to clearly convey God's revelation to all believers.

Remarkably, in his first speech as Speaker of the House, when he was first elected, Johnson suggested that his becoming Speaker was ordained by God:  "I believe that scripture, the Bible, is very clear that God is the one that raises up those in authority. He raised up each of you. All of us. And I believe that God has allowed and ordained each and every one of us to be here at this specific moment. This is my belief."  

Well, okay, this is his belief.  But how does he know that that this is a true belief coming from the Holy Spirit?  Other Christians in the tradition of Roger Williams would say that the New Testament does not support the kind of Mosaic theocracy found in the Old Testament, that New Testament Christianity demands a wall of separation between church and state, and therefore that it is blasphemy to say that God has chosen Donald Trump to be President.  How can Johnson be sure that these Christians are wrong?