Here's the text of my remarks, which consist largely of excerpts from my article in the Fall 2010 issue of The Intercollegiate Review.
If
we accept evolutionary science, then human nature is not one of the permanent things. But it is one of the enduring things. And that’s
enough.
An
evolved human nature that is enduring but not permanent is enough to support an
evolutionary conservatism rooted in an
evolutionary moral anthropology of natural desires, customary traditions, and
individual judgments.
That’s
not enough, however, for a metaphysical
conservatism that appeals to a transcendent moral cosmology of eternal order as
intelligently designed by the Creator.
This
contrast between evolutionary conservatism and metaphysical conservatism was
displayed in the debate between Friedrich Hayek and Russell Kirk at the 1957
meeting of the Mont Pelerin Society.
Kirk
had stated his metaphysical and religious conservatism in 1953 in The Conservative Mind. The first canon of conservative thought,
he declared, was “belief that a divine intent rules society as well as
conscience, forging an eternal chain of right and duty which links great and
obscure, living and dead.” Consequently,
“politics is the art of apprehending and applying the Justice which is above
nature.” Kirk spoke of the conservative
belief in “a transcendent moral order,” and in Edmund Burke’s “description of
the state as a divinely ordained moral essence, a spiritual union of the dead,
the living, and those yet unborn,” and Kirk also spoke of Burke’s view of
history as “the unfolding of Design.”
Kirk warned against Darwinian evolutionary science as undermining this
metaphysical conservatism because it denies the religious belief in a
transcendent moral order of intelligent design.
In
this same tradition of metaphysical conservatism, Richard Weaver insisted that
a healthy cultural order required a “metaphysical dream of the world,” so that
people could imagine their cultural life as a “metaphysical community”
fulfilling a cosmic purpose. Like Kirk,
Weaver worried that Darwin’s theory of evolution denied this “metaphysical
dream” of cosmic order by explaining human beings as products of a natural
evolutionary process governed by material causes that were not directed to any
cosmic purposes. Consequently, in the
Darwinian view, human cultural order was deprived of any transcendent meaning
because it could not be seen as serving the cosmic order of the Creator’s
intelligently designed universe.
Since
Hayek accepted Darwinian science but doubted the existence of God, he disagreed
with Kirk’s metaphysical conservatism.
This led Hayek to insist—at the 1957 meeting—that he was not really a
“conservative” at all, but a “liberal” in the classical tradition of Burke and
the Old Whigs. He objected to the
“obscurantism” of a conservative attitude that rejected Darwin’s theory of
evolution as morally corrupting. He
elaborated his view of Burkean liberalism as belonging to a British empiricist evolutionary
tradition contrasted with a French rationalistic design tradition. In the evolutionary tradition of David Hume, Adam
Smith, and Burke, Hayek explained, “it was shown that an evident order which
was not the product of a designing human intelligence need not therefore be
ascribed to the design of a higher, supernatural intelligence, but that there
was a third possibility—the emergence of order as the result of adaptive
evolution.” He then suggested that
Darwin’s theory of biological evolution was derived from the theories of social
evolution developed by the Scottish philosophers.
That
both Kirk and Hayek appealed to Burke suggests that they were both Burkean
liberal conservatives. But their
disagreement reflects a tension within Burke’s political thought, with Kirk
embracing the metaphysical side of Burke’s conservatism, and Hayek embracing
the evolutionary side.
The
evolutionary tradition of social thought was deepened by Charles Darwin,
particularly in his Descent of Man,
in his explanation of moral order as rooted in a moral sense that is part of
the evolved nature of human beings. He
saw moral progress in human history as a product of the complex evolutionary
interaction of innate sociality, cultural learning, and deliberate judgment. “Ultimately,” he concluded, “our moral sense
or conscience becomes a highly complex sentiment—originating in the social
instincts, largely guided by the approbation of our fellow-men, ruled by
reason, self-interest, and in later times by deep religious feelings, and
confirmed by instruction and habit.” Darwin
observed that this moral sense “perhaps affords the best and highest
distinction between man and the lower animals.”
In
recent years, new research in evolutionary social psychology and Darwinian
anthropology has renewed interest in how evolutionary science might support
classical liberalism or traditionalist conservatism. One sign of this was the special meeting of
the Mont Pelerin Society last summer in the Galapagos Islands exploring the
topic of “Evolution, the Human Sciences, and Liberty.”
Any renewal of evolutionary conservatism will provoke criticisms from the
metaphysical conservatives. From my
experience in defending Darwinian conservatism, the most common criticism is
that the naturalist morality of Darwinian science must fail, because a healthy
moral order depends necessarily on religion, and particularly on the biblical
doctrine that all human beings are created in God’s image and thus endowed by
their Creator with equal moral dignity.
For
example, my critics have argued, the moral condemnation of slavery arose from a
religious metaphysics that saw slavery as contrary to God’s law. A purely naturalistic Darwinian morality
would not have taught us that slavery is absolutely wrong.
But
is this true? Darwin was a fervent
opponent of slavery. Like Hume and
Smith, he saw slavery as a violation of the moral sentiments—particularly,
those sentiments that enforce justice as reciprocity.
From
an evolutionary perspective, slavery is a form of social parasitism. And since human slaves are not naturally
adapted to their enslavement, they will resist exploitation, and slaveholders
will have to impose their rule over their slaves by force and fraud.
In
the effort to justify slavery, American slaveholders espoused a fraudulent ideology
of paternalism that claimed that the slaves were naturally benefited by their
enslavement. The proslavery ideology in
the American South asserted that black slaves were physically, morally, and
intellectually inferior to whites in their biological nature, and so these
black slaves were happier when they were serving white masters.
One
of the primary motivations for Darwin’s writing of The Descent of Man was to refute this ideology of scientific racism
by showing that all the human races were members of the same human species with
the same moral sense that condemned slavery as exploitation.
American Southern
conservatives defended slavery as a conservative Christian institution
supported by the Bible. In writing about
Southern conservatism, in The Conservative Mind, Kirk warned that “human slavery is bad ground for
conservatives to make a stand upon.” But
he never answered the arguments of the Southern Christian conservatives that
slavery was biblically sanctioned as part of God’s law.
Richard
Weaver admired the “older religiousness” in the American South before the Civil
War, and he recognized that part of the Southern religion was faith in the
Bible as supporting slavery. Weaver
explained that slavery “is well recognized in the Old Testament, and it is not
without endorsement in the New; indeed, a strict constructionist interpretation
almost requires its defense.” So it
seems that the “metaphysical dream of the world” in the Old South sanctioned
slavery as part of God’s transcendent moral order.
The
dispute over the Bible’s handling of the slavery issue divided the Christian
churches in America before and during the Civil War. Americans had looked to the Bible as the
revelation of the sacred order of the universe that would resolve all moral
disputes by the cosmic authority of God’s law.
But in this greatest moral crisis in American history, the Bible failed
to provide any satisfactory answer in the dispute over slavery between North
and South. As Abraham Lincoln observed
in his Second Inaugural Address, “Both read the same Bible, and pray to the
same God, and each invokes His aid against the other.”
In
such a situation, human beings must appeal to some natural moral sense like
that espoused by Hume, Smith, and Darwin.
Darwinian conservatives can explain this moral sense as rooted in
evolved human nature. Unlike the
metaphysical conservatives, who claim that all social order must conform to
some supernatural order of intelligent design or divine creation, evolutionary
conservatives see social order as the product of ordinary human experience as
guided by nature, custom, and prudence.
So
as we celebrate the permanent things, let’s not forget the enduring things,
which include the enduring human structure of instinctive evolution, cultural
evolution, and individual judgment that gives us an enduring standard of
natural right.
For
those of us who are Darwinian conservatives, that’s enough.