Recently, Behavioral and Brain Sciences has published an article by Pascal Boyer--"Ownership Psychology as a Cognitive Adaptation"--along with 31 commentaries on the article and Boyer's response. I wrote one of the commentaries.
Here I will provide Boyer's abstract for his article, my commentary, and then some comments on the argument for self-ownership in some of the other commentaries and Boyer's response.
BOYER'S ABSTRACT
"Ownership is universal and ubiquitous in human societies, yet the psychology underpinning ownership intuitions is generally not described in a coherent and computationally tractable manner. Ownership intuitions are commonly assumed to derive from culturally transmitted social norms, or from a mentally represented implicit theory. While the social norms account is entirely ad hoc, the mental theory requires prior assumptions about possession and ownership that must be explained. Here I propose such an explanation, arguing the intuitions result from the interaction of two cognitive systems. One of these handles competitive interactions for the possession of resources observed in many species including humans. The other handles mutually beneficial cooperation between agents, as observed in communal sharing, collective action, and trade. Together, these systems attend to specific cues in the environment, and produce definite intuitions such as 'this is hers,' 'that is not mine.' This computational model provides an explanation for ownership intuitions, not just in straightforward cases of property, but also in disputed ownership (squatters, indigenous rights), historical changes (abolition of slavery), as well as apparently marginal cases, such as the questions, whether people own their seats on the bus, or their places in a queue, and how people understand 'cultural appropriation' and slavery. In contrast to some previous theories, the model is empirically testable and free of ad hoc stipulations" (Pascal 2023).
MY COMMENTARY
The psychology
of ownership is rooted in self-ownership.
The human brain has an evolved interoceptive sense of owning the body
that supports self-ownership and the ownership of external things as extensions
of the self-owning self. In this way,
evolutionary neuroscience supports a Lockean liberal conception of equal
natural rights rooted in natural self-ownership.
Boyer argues persuasively for the interaction of two cognitive systems to explain the psychology of ownership. But in doing this, he fails to recognize that there is a third cognitive system for self-ownership that is the true root of the evolutionary psychology of ownership. In explaining “the interaction of cognitive systems that are not about ownership as such,” Pascal ignores the evolved intuitive psychology of self-ownership, which really is “about ownership as such.”
At the center of Boyer’s model is the “conceptual tag”
of “(Agent, thing).” This assumes
without explanation that human beings have an intuitive sense of themselves as agents
who claim ownership of things.
He provides no evolutionary explanation for why and how human beings
have this intuition. The best
explanation for this is the evolved neurobiology of self-ownership and
self-owning agency: if human beings did not have any sense of owning
themselves, they could not claim ownership of things external to them as
extensions of their self-owning selves.
John Locke saw that the natural desire for ownership
or property was rooted in the natural psychology of self-ownership—that “every
Man has a Property in his own Person,” and this “no Body has any Right to but
himself” (1988, 287). Boyer points to
Locke’s theory of property in explaining why labor is relevant to
ownership. But Boyer fails to see the
importance of Locke’s claim about self-ownership in supporting the natural
right to property as the fundamental principle of Lockean liberalism, and how evolutionary
psychology can explain this as grounded in the evolved neurobiology of the
human brain.
Lockean liberals have seen slavery—the institution by
which one person can own another person—as the most radical denial of the
natural right of everyone to own oneself.
In considering the case of slavery, Boyer explains abolitionism as a
widening of the “moral circle” to include slaves, but he does not acknowledge
that at the center of that “moral circle” is the self-owning human being recognizing
other human beings as self-owners.
This was made clear by abolitionists such as Frederick
Douglass, who ran away from his enslavement and became a leading abolitionist
orator. Douglass said that even in
childhood, he held onto one idea for freedom and against slavery: “Every man is
the original, rightful, and absolute owner of his own body; or in other
words, every man is himself, is his self, if you please, and belongs to
himself, and can only part from his self-ownership, by the commission of
a crime” (1991, 42).
Now we can see how this sense of each person’s
self-ownership arises in the evolved neuroanatomy of the brain to serve the
survival and well-being of the human animal.
We can understand this as expressing interoception—the neural perception
of the state of the body (Ceunen, Vlaeyen, & Van Diest 2016; Tsakiris &
De Preester 2019).
The research on interoception shows that our self-awareness
arises from the feelings that we have from our bodies as a neural integration
in insular cortex of the signals of the condition of the body. The interoceptive neural network, having its
core in the anterior insular cortex and the anterior cingulate cortex, provides
the basis for the subjective awareness of our bodily emotions and social
feelings, including pleasure, anxiety, trust, and anger (Craig 2015).
The brain’s interoceptive feeling of self-ownership
includes feeling whether other people are likely to be helpful or harmful to
oneself, as in the brain’s ability to discriminate trustworthy faces and
untrustworthy faces, or the propensisty to punish people who make unfair offers
in an Ultimatum Game. Our brains evolved
to protect ourselves from threats and to seek out cooperative relationships in
ways that secure our survival and well-being.
This explains the evolved basis in the brain for
Douglass’s Lockean liberal principle of self-ownership in human nature. In running away from his slave master, and
then in arguing for the abolition of slavery, Douglass expressed the evolved
natural propensity of the human brain for self-ownership and for moral
resentment against those who would threaten the natural human right to
self-ownership. Moreover, Douglass
extended this liberal principle of natural human equality in self-ownership to
support other natural human rights—including women’s rights, the rights of
immigrants, and religious liberty (Buccola 2012).
Brain disorders can disrupt this sense of bodily
self-ownership. One example of this is somatoparaphrenia
(derived from three Greek words denoting “body outside the mind”). People who have had strokes in the right
hemisphere of the brain sometimes suffer through a short period in which they
deny that their left leg or arm belongs to them. They can see that their left arm or
left leg is attached to their body, but it doesn’t feel like it’s part
of their body (Antoniello & Gottesman 2017; Feinberg et al. 2010; Gandola
et al. 2012; Vallar & Ronchi 2009).
Comparing the studies of somatoparaphrenia, similar bodily
disorders, and illusions such as the rubber hand illusion, in which the brain
is tricked into feeling that a rubber hand is one’s own hand, provides evidence
for what Frédérique de Vignemont (2020) calls the Bodyguard Hypothesis: the brain
has evolved to protect the body through neural circuits that have a protective
body map that creates a sense of bodily ownership and affective motivation to
behave in ways that protect the body identified in the body map. Syndromes of disowning one’s body occur when the
body map does not represent a limb that feels alien. Illusions of body ownership occur when the
body map mistakenly represents something as a body part.
Evolution by natural selection favors those
psychological propensities rooted in the brain that enhance our chances for
self-preservation, which includes a sense of personal identity expressed in our
owning and protecting our bodies, and then extending that sense of
self-ownership into the ownership of external property that belongs to us. In this way, evolutionary neuroscience
supports a Lockean liberal conception of equal natural rights rooted in natural
self-ownership (Arnhart 1995, 1998, 2016).
References
Antoniello,
D., & Gottesman, R. (2017) Limb misidentification: A clinical-anatomical prospective
study. Journal of Neuropsychiatry and Clinical Neuroscience 29:284-88.
Arnhart,
L. (1995) The new Darwinian naturalism in political theory. American
Political Science Review 89:389-400.
Arnhart,
L. (1998) Darwinian natural right: The biological ethics of human nature.
The State University of New York Press.
Arnhart,
L. (2016) Political questions: Political philosophy from Plato to Pinker. Waveland Press.
Boyer, Pascal. (2023) Ownership psychology as a cognitive adaptation: A minimalist model. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 46, e323: 1-68. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X22002527
Buccola, N. (2012) The
political thought of Frederick Douglass.
New York University Press.
Ceunen, E., Vlaeyen, J., & Van Diest, I. (2016)
On the origin of interoception. Frontiers
in Psychology 7:743.
Craig, A. D. (2015) How
do you feel? An interoceptive moment with your neurobiological self. Princeton University Press.
de Vignemont, F. (2020) Mind
the body: An exploration of bodily self-awareness. Oxford University Press.
Douglass, F. (1991) The
Frederick Douglass papers: Volume 4,
ed. J. W. Blassingame & J. R. McKivigan. Yale University Press.
Feinberg, T., Venneri, A., Simone, A. M., Fan, Y.,
& Northoff, G. (2010) The neuroanatomy of asomatognosia and
somatoparaphrenia. Journal
of Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry 81:276-81.
Gandola, M., Invernizzi, P., Sedda, A., Ferre, E.
R., Sterzi, R., Sherna, M., Paulesu, E., & Bottini, G. (2012) An anatomical
account of somatoparaphrenia. Cortex 48:1165-78.
Locke, J. (1988) Two
treatises of government. Cambridge
University Press.
Tsakiris, M., & De Preester, H., eds. (2019) The interoceptive mind: From
homeostasis to awareness. Oxford
University Press.
Vallar, G., & Ronchi, R. (2009) Somatoparaphrenia: A body delusion. A review of the neuropsychological literature. Experimental Brain Research 192:533-51.
BOYER'S RESPONSE TO THE ARGUMENT FOR SELF-OWNERSHIP
I was surprised to see that 7 of the 31 commentaries agreed with my argument for rooting the moral right to ownership in self-ownership (Hood 2023; Kemmerer 2023; Merker 2023; Nancekivell and Pesowski 2023; Rochat 2023; Starmans 2023; Wispinski, Enns, and Chapman 2023). Some of the commentators express this idea as understanding owned items as components of the "extended self." Others express this explicitly as ownership founded in our sense of our ownership of our bodies.
Boyer rejects this by arguing: "we do not need to postulate any psychological processes, beyond two mechanisms (competitive acquisition and mutualistic cooperation) that are already independently documented in a vast literature. By contrast, the extended-body or extended-self metaphors are additional mechanisms postulated specifically in order to explain ownership phenomena" (Boyer 2023, 61).
But this does not refute my argument that Boyer's "conceptual tag" of "(Agent, thing)" assumes without explanation that human beings have an intuitive sense of themselves as agents who claim ownership of things. The best explanation for this is the evolved neurobiology of self-ownership and self-owning agency.
In his one attempt to answer my argument, Boyer says that he can provide an evolutionary explanation for intuitions of associations between agents and things by saying that there were selective pressures in early human evolution that would have favored recognizing the claims of agents to the ownership of territories and tools, and he cites the commentary by Merker.
But Boyer is silent about the fact that Merker grounds this ownership psychology in "our sense of ownership of our bodies as the central invariant of resource acquisition," and from there "the sense of ownership extends out, on a species-specific basis, to various extra-corporeal objects and circumstances in which a sense of ownership may be invested." And so, for example, when our early human ancestors invested labor and deliberate effort in fashioning stone tools, they would have claimed ownership of those tools (Merker 2023, 41-42).
References
Hood, Bruce. 2023. "Ownership as a Component of the Extended Self." BBS 46, e323: 36-37.
Kemmerer, David. 2023. "Ownership Language Informs Ownership Psychology." BBS 46, e323: 39-40.
Merker, Bjorn. 2023. "Invested Effort and Our Open-Ended Sense of Ownership." BBS 46, e323: 41-42.
Nancekivell, Shaylene E., and Madison Pesowski. 2023. "Ownership as an Extension of Self: An Alternative to a Minimalist Model." BBS 46, e323: 45-47.
Rochat, Philippe. 2023. "Primordial Feeling of Possession in Development." BBS 46, e323: 49-50.
Starmans, Christina. 2023. "Autonomy, the Moral Circle, and the Limits of Ownership." BBS 46. e323: 52-53.
Wispinski, Nathan J., James T. Enns, and Craig S. Chapman. 2023. "Hold It! Where Do We Put the Body?" BBS 46, e323: 57-59.
Is Boyer denying that human beings experience a sense of ownership of their bodies? Or does he grant that, but assume that the sense of ownership of things has an entirely different basis?
ReplyDeleteAs his subtitle indicates, he insists on the virtues of his "minimalist model" such that one can explain ownership from only two mechanisms--competitive acquisition and mutualistic cooperation. So he implies that even if there is some psychology of self-ownership, it can be explained as arising from these two mechanisms.
ReplyDelete