In preparation for the International Adam Smith Society conference in Bogota, Columbia, July 11-13, I have been reading some papers on Adam Smith and Bernard Mandeville. This has stimulated me to think more about Smith's comments on Mandeville, particularly regarding Christian ethics. I foresee that in some of the discussions in Bogota, I will suggest a way of reading Smith’s response to Mandeville that differs from readings offered by others at the conference.
I see Smith as an esoteric writer, who
conveys a surface teaching that differs from his secret
teaching. His surface teaching will be
popular with his orthodox Christian readers.
His secret teaching will be unpopular with those readers. He felt compelled to write this way to avoid
persecution.
The clearest evidence for this is the one time in his life
in which he publicly, if only momentarily, removed the cloak of esotericism—his
Letter to William Strahan in 1776 on the life and death of David
Hume. In the last paragraph of that
letter, Smith identified Hume as “a perfectly wise and virtuous man,” which
meant that an irreligious skeptic could be morally and intellectually
virtuous.
This
provoked an angry reaction from Christians that lasted for the rest of Smith’s
life and even after his death. As John
Ramsey of Ochtertyre wrote at the time, the Letter to Strahan “gave very
great offence, and made [Smith] henceforth be regarded as an avowed skeptic, to
the no small regret of many who revered his character and admired his
writings.”
Seeing Smith as an esoteric writer allows us to explain the
complexity of his comments on Mandeville.
His surface teaching was that Mandeville’s moral theory was
“licentious” and “erroneous,” because Mandeville was deceptive in identifying
all self-love as vanity, and because he mistakenly defined all virtue as
“complete self-denial,” so that what were popularly thought to be virtues were
disguised vices.
Smith’s secret teaching, however, was that
Mandeville correctly saw that all virtue was motivated by proud self-love, and
therefore that the Christian definition of virtue as humble self-denial and
“ascetic abstinence” was wrong. Although
Mandeville’s surface teaching assumed the Christian definition of
virtue, Mandeville’s secret teaching in The Fable of the Bees was
a comic satire of Christian virtue that employed a reductio ad absurdum argument
to refute the Christian understanding of virtue. It was this secret teaching of Mandeville
and Smith that allowed Smith to identify Hume as “a perfectly wise and virtuous
man.”
Christian theologians—like Saint Augustine in The City
of God, for example—had long taught that all human beings were by nature so
depraved by the original sin of pride that they could never be truly virtuous
in their earthly life. The worldly pretense of virtue is corrupted by a proud
“self-love, even to the contempt of God.”
True virtue could be achieved only through a humble “love of God, even
to the contempt of self” (14.28).
Therefore, Augustine insisted, there can be no true virtues without true religion. In their natural experience of social life,
human beings want to be virtuous because they want to be praised for their
virtues to satisfy their self-love. But
virtues motivated by this self-loving desire for praise are really vices not virtues. Even those who seek virtue for its own
sake—to be praiseworthy regardless of whether anyone actually praises them—are
still moved by the self-loving desire for human praise, even if only in
praising themselves for being praiseworthy.
True virtue is achieved only through humble self-abnegation in
submitting to the transcendent law of God that promises eternal salvation in
the afterlife (19.25).
This
Christian understanding of virtue denies the ancient teaching of pagan
philosophers like Aristotle that the good man should love himself, that the
“great-souled” or magnanimous man should be properly proud of himself, and that
humility is not a virtue (TMS, 258-59).
It is notable, therefore, that Smith identifies Aristotle’s account of
virtue as corresponding “pretty exactly” with his own (TMS, 270-72).
As Smith suggested, even if only by subtle implication,
Mandeville correctly saw the mistakes in this Christian understanding of virtue
and vice (TMS, 308-14).
Mandeville saw that if vanity is the desire for undeserved praise, then,
according to the Christian doctrine of total human depravity, all self-loving
desires for praise or praiseworthiness are vanity, because no human beings
deserve praise for their self-loving conduct.
Mandeville also saw that according to the Christian definition of true
virtue as “complete self-denial” and “the entire extirpation and annihilation
of all our passions,” such virtue could never be achieved among men, and any
pretense of such virtue was fraudulent.
Moreover, even if such perfect Christian virtue could be achieved, this
would be “pernicious to society.” That’s
why, as Mandeville famously and scandalously declared, “private vices are public benefits.”
1 comment:
Both sides are wrong, that is Augustine/Augustinians and Atheists. Their extreme views breed the opposite extreme, and were edtablished by Satan to continually produce that effect. Its similar to anti-Trinitarianism and the extreme false Trinitarianism of the falsely titled "Athanasian" creed. Satan established both to support each other mutally by being so extreme as to cause people to jump from one to the other but always skip the true Trinitarianism of the Nicene Creed in the middle. So here also its either belief in total depravity or total goodness jumping directly over the middle taughg by individuals false Christianity designed by Satan and promulgated by Augustine declared heretical who were in fact saints and taught what the Bible really says.
Post a Comment