In the middle of July, I will be in Bogota, Columbia, for the 2022 Conference of the International Adam Smith Society. I will present a paper entitled "The Three Waves of Adam Smith's Darwinian Liberal Moral Theory." Here is a short summary of a long paper:
I have argued that we should see Charles
Darwin, Edward Westermarck, and Edward O. Wilson as the three waves of Adam
Smith’s Darwinian liberal theory, because each of them initiated a new turn in
the evolutionary moral psychology that has confirmed and deepened Smith’s liberal
theory of the moral sentiments.
I
have identified this as a liberal moral theory for three reasons. It assumes a liberal individualism that recognizes
the natural separateness of individuals and the moral claims that individuals
make. It asserts the liberal no-harm
principle of justice as a “negative virtue” that hinders individuals from any
unprovoked harming of others. And it employs
the liberal idea of society as a largely self-regulating and spontaneous order
arising from the social interaction of individuals seeking to satisfy their
individual desires.
I
have defended this as an empiricist moral anthropology that arises from the
coevolution of human nature, human culture, and human judgment. This revives an ancient Greek liberal
evolutionary tradition that is set against the traditional Platonic idea that
moral order must conform to some transcendentalist moral cosmology of a cosmic
God, a cosmic Reason, or a cosmic Nature.
In The Theory of Moral Sentiments,
Smith did often invoke the transcendentalist moral cosmology of a moral
divinity enforcing a divine moral law through eternal rewards and punishments. But as Smith made clear in his praise of Hume
as “a perfectly wise and virtuous man,” Smith was an esoteric writer whose
public teaching of religious morality had concealed from most of his readers
his philosophic teaching that irreligious skeptics like Hume could be wise and
virtuous.
I have shown how evolutionary moral psychology
supports Smith’s theory of moral sentiments through seven ideas: the four grounds of evolutionary morality, the
evolutionary roots of morality in primates, the expression of the instinctive moral
sentiments in human children, the moral psychology of the impartial spectator in
evolutionary game theory, the evolutionary science of the universal moral rule
condemning incest, the evolutionary morals of markets, and the evolutionary
history of trade as expressing the natural human “propensity to truck, barter,
and exchange.”
I have replied to the two most common
objections to evolutionary ethics. One objection
is that evolutionary moral psychology is ultimately nihilistic in promoting the
idea that morality is a fictional creation of the human mind that does not
conform to any eternal reality of moral facts inscribed in the cosmic order of
the world. My response to this objection
has been to argue that while an evolutionary sentimentalist morality is created
by the human mind, that does not make morality arbitrary or fictional. The human morality of the natural moral
sentiments is real: although it is not
an eternal reality, it is an enduring reality that will endure for as long as our
evolved human nature endures.
The second objection is that evolutionary
ethics commits the “naturalistic fallacy” by assuming that moral values can be
inferred from natural facts. My reply
has been to argue that there is no fallacy in understanding moral judgments to
be factual judgments about the species-typical pattern of moral sentiments in
specified circumstances: it is natural for
human beings that certain moral feelings of approbation or disapprobation tend
to be aroused by certain facts, and the experience of such feelings is the only
ground for our moral judgments.
From
all of this, we can see that a Darwinian liberal theory of the Smithian moral
sentiments offers us one way of understanding our human place in nature. We are neither mindless machines nor disembodied
spirits. We are animals. As animals, shaped by our natural
evolutionary history as primates, we display the animate powers of nature for
movement, desire, and awareness. We move
to satisfy our desires in the light of our awareness of the world. We are a unique species of animal, but our
distinctively human traits—such as symbolic speech, practical deliberation, and
conceptual thought—are emergent elaborations of powers shared in some form with
other animals. Our powers for
habituation and learning allow us to alter our natural environments, but even
these powers are emergent extensions of the behavioral flexibility shown by
other animals. So even if the natural
world was not made for us, we were made for it, because we are adapted to live
in it. We have not been thrown into
nature from some place far away. We come
from nature. It is our home.
Great piece. Will be very interested to hear about the reactions at the conference. Any idea when the full paper will be published?
ReplyDeleteI have no idea about publishing it. It's way too long to be published as an article, and too short to be published as a book. If it's well received at the conference, someone might suggest some route to publication.
ReplyDelete"So even if the natural world was not made for us, we were made for it, because we are adapted to live in it. We have not been thrown into nature from some place far away. We come from nature. It is our home."
ReplyDeleteNot as poetic as "there is grandeur ..." but pretty good and a nice summary.