While reading Professor Arnhart’s bracing review of my book on
Strauss, I kept recalling the oft-quoted words of John Adams: “Facts are
stubborn things.” The gist of Arnhart’s critique of my book seems to be that my
historicist argument that Straussianism is essentially wrong to teach that
there is a universal human desire for liberal democracy (regardless of faith,
history, or culture) is unpersuasive because my thesis does not fit into the
theory of evolution that Arnhart has popularly applied to the history and
content of political philosophy. In brief, I am apparently wrong to dismiss
this ideology of democratic universalism that Straussians usually teach because
I set up a false dichotomy between nature and history. My insistence that
bourgeois Protestant Christianity is a necessary precondition for successful
constitutional self-government apparently flies in the face of liberal regimes
that are not rooted in this faith tradition. Arnhart asks the rhetorical
question: “Isn’t this historical evidence for the universal appeal of
liberalism, suggesting that liberalism really does conform to a universal human
nature?” Strauss’s teaching that liberal democracy is the best regime for all
human beings must be correct, then, according to Arnhart, because both nature and history support it.
I find it curious
that Arnhart does not give much attention to the reasons why I make this
historicist argument. Most of my book develops the argument that Strauss and
his many students erroneously tried to locate the true origins of liberal
democracy in Greek political philosophy, particularly Plato and Aristotle. This
reading of ancient political thought is crucial to the Straussian assumption,
which Arnhart shares, that human beings by
nature seek the best political regime. In the process, they can argue that
democracy is the universally best regime for humanity. Yet I show in my book
that this central assumption is false because the ancient Greek concept of
democracy never allowed for certain virtues that are crucial to successful
self-government: these include Christian virtues such as charity (love thy
neighbor, and even one’s enemy, as one loves God) as well as humility and
mercy. The best evidence for the unnatural status of these virtues is that the
greatest Greek philosophers did not even account for them, based on their own
philosophies of nature. This fact was sometimes recognized by Strauss himself,
who, as I show in the last chapter of my book, rigorously distinguished the
moral teachings of “Athens,” or Greek political philosophy, from “Jerusalem,”
biblical revelation. Until the Christian Era, which includes early modernity,
the assumption that charity is a necessary precondition for a peaceful, stable,
and humane government was absent in the works of political philosophers who
followed Plato and Aristotle. The ancient Greek tolerance of slavery,
infanticide, and natural hierarchy held no place for the ethic of caritas, a fact that was well-known to
social contract theorists such as Hobbes, Spinoza, and Locke. (It is also
central to Hegel’s philosophy of history.) Only in a specific historical
period, as opposed to nature, then, do we find evidence of a regime that rises
above nature to embody, however imperfectly, an ethic of charity.
I recount all these
facts because of Arnhart’s Darwinian-Straussian thesis that it is false to set
up a dichotomy between nature and history. Apparently, Christian charity is
just as natural as the desire for liberal democracy, according to my reviewer.
To anyone who is familiar with the biblical tradition, the first assumption is
shocking in its naiveté. If it is natural for human beings to love each other,
why does our sinful nature so regularly conflict with this natural moral
desire? And, why did the social contractarians cited above similarly insist
that there is neither charity nor government in the “state of nature,” the
natural order of humanity, if charity is so closely aligned with our instincts?
(I must confess to a strong Protestant bias here about the fallenness of humanity
as well as the sheer difficulty that human beings have in practicing charity on
a consistent basis.)
Arnhart, of course,
will have none of this. His first specific objection to my argument is that I
too harshly limit the universal morality of Christianity to the particular
foundation of liberal Protestantism, even though I also inconsistently claim
that Christian charity has great influence beyond this modern foundation. How
can a morality be universal without being historically universal as well? My answer
to this objection is that Arnhart is confusing moral universalism with historical
universalism. It is one thing to claim that all human beings ought to be
charitable. It is quite another to assert that all traditions in history have
practiced or even understood charity. Arnhart confuses the “ought” with the
“is” here because his adherence to the theory of evolution forces him into this
theoretical cul-de-sac: if charity is not historically universal (that is
natural), then it cannot be naturally intelligible to all human beings.
Evolutionism, then, is inadequate in trying to explain how charity emerged
naturally. (Arnhart presumably does not agree with his fellow evolutionist
Richard Dawkins that Christian charity is so unnatural that only “suckers” would
practice this ethic.) Arnhart can always fall back on his view that human
nature and human history are equally influential, but that tactic is just
question-begging. Which is most influential?
Additionally, how does
evolution, in Arnhart’s own words, explain how “some historical traditions show
a better grasp of human nature than do other historical traditions”? How indeed
would evolution explain the fact that Athens, one of the founding traditions of
the West, lacked a concept of charity if the latter ethic is natural? Why did
it take so long for this ethic to be applied to politics, culminating in the
creation of modern self-government, if it is all so natural and universal? How
can we avoid the fact that Jerusalem, not Athens, makes possible the historical
rise of charity as it is applied to politics?
Arnhart’s response to
all this is that “many different religious and philosophical traditions have
discovered the Golden Rule (charity) as a reasonable inference from natural
human experience” and cites C. S. Lewis’s famous argument in defence of natural
law as the “Tao” that all human
beings understand by nature. This assertion, to say the least, requires
evidence. Although all religions teach some concept of moral obligation,
Christianity is unique in teaching that love and obligation extend to one’s
enemy, a teaching that is consistent with the Christian emphasis on mercy and
humility. Arnhart would have to show how the pagan texts of antiquity,
including those of Plato and Aristotle, contain these virtues. (Arnhart’s
fellow Straussian Harry Jaffa, in his Thomism
and Aristotelianism [1952], brought out this distinction between Jerusalem
and Athens with great insight.) In Plato’s famous dialogue on love, The Symposium, the reader will look in
vain for any expression of love akin to charity. Confucianism, which at a
superficial level teaches moral obligation towards other human beings,
generally restricts this sense of duty to one’s family. (Christ’s famous
condemnation of family-based love in Luke 14:26 would be shocking to a
Confucian.) Since charity teaches the love of both God and humanity, any religion or philosophy that dualistically opposes
one to the other (either love God or
humanity) is incompatible with Christian morality.
I am not, of course,
claiming that all Christians in history have adhered to this demanding ethic
with perfect consistency. Arnhart is quite right to point out that
abolitionists and slave-owners in the decades leading up to the American Civil
War profoundly disagreed as to whether Scripture, including the Christian
teaching on charity, opposed slavery or not. How, then, asks Arnhart, can I
appeal to the Bible for guidance or claim that the Golden Rule was the
foundation of Abraham Lincoln’s opposition to slavery when Americans on both
sides of the Mason-Dixon line claimed to be good Christians? My answer, which I
develop in detail in Lincoln and the
Politics of Christian Love (2009), is that the 16th president
never doubted that a true application
of Christian charity was incompatible with slavery. Since no slave-owner would
ever choose to be a slave, he could not justifiably enslave another human
being. Yet Southern slave-owners sinfully and wilfully denied this moral truth
even as they falsely projected onto the Bible a violently uncharitable
rationale for slavery. Lincoln knew all too well that human beings were
naturally inclined to enslave each other and to reject the “self-evident”
nature of human equality. For this reason, he appealed to that most unnatural,
yet humane, expressions of morality: charity.
Arnhart nevertheless
claims to have the facts on his side when he confidently recounts the
“historical trend towards the spread of liberalism” around the world since the
Enlightenment. (Ironically, this progressivist argument would not have sat well
with Strauss, who absolutely opposed any appeal to the “march of progress” as a
justification for a prudent politics.) He goes on to claim that many of these
“liberal regimes are clearly not rooted in the historical tradition of liberal
Protestant culture” such as Japan, Malaysia, and South Korea. These examples,
however, do not exactly confirm his thesis since all three of these nations had
some significant exposure to English or American ideals due to the influence of
occupation, colonization, or war. What is shocking in this discussion is
Arnhart’s deafening silence on the failure of liberal democracy to take root in
most nations of the Middle East. If liberal democracy is so natural, then why
has the Arab Spring become the Arab Winter? Could the grim oscillation between
theocracy and dictatorship have anything to do with a distinct religious and
historical tradition? And recent wars for democracy in Iraq, Afghanistan, and
Libya have not exactly confirmed Arnhart’s optimistic view that all the peoples
of the world are itching for constitutional government and the rule of law. But
then again, history is full of inconvenient truths that do not fill well into
ideological boxes.
"the 16th president never doubted that a true application of Christian charity was incompatible with slavery. ... Yet Southern slave-owners sinfully and wilfully denied this moral truth even as they falsely projected onto the Bible a violently uncharitable rationale for slavery."
ReplyDeleteSo it's not just "that bourgeois Protestant Christianity is a necessary precondition for successful constitutional self-government," it must be true bourgeois Protestant Christianity.
No doubt this is unfair but I can't help thinking of the people who reject the idea that Russia, China, etc. tell us anything about socialism. Because, you see, they aren't true socialism.
A definition of 'charity and christian charity' would be helpful. So that one can understand whether it is existence in either philosophical tradition as currently understood or does it need some other frame.
ReplyDelete