This essay has appeared in the fall 2013 issue of the Claremont Review of Books.
The Social Conquest of Earth, by Edward O. Wilson.
Liveright Publishing, 331 pages, $27.95
Paul Gauguin's most famous painting shows some human figures set in a Tahitian landscape. They display the human life cycle from infancy to adulthood to old age. One corner of the painting has three questions: Where do we come from? What are we? Where are we going?
To answer these
fundamental questions about our human place in the cosmos, Edward O. Wilson
suggests in his new book, we need to unify all our knowledge of nature by combining
the natural sciences, the social sciences, and the humanities.
Traditionally, we have looked to religion, philosophy, or the creative
arts to answer these great questions. Wilson argues that these three
ways to understand the human condition have failed. This leaves science--in
its quest for a complete knowledge of nature--as the only way to understand the
human story.
Wilson separates
philosophy from science, because he assumes that philosophy must rely
purely on introspection and logic without any of the empirical research that is
done by scientists. He thus turns away from what he said in an earlier
book—Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge--where he recognized that the
search for consilience, understood as the unification of all knowledge of
nature, began in Greek antiquity with
Thales of Miletus and Aristotle. Until recently, there was no separation
between philosophy and science, and what we call "natural science"
today was previously called "natural philosophy." Aristotle was
particularly important as a biologist who saw moral and political philosophy as
a biological science. Wilson acknowledged this in Consilience,
when he identified his biological science of ethics and politics as continuing
the empiricist tradition of Aristotle, David Hume, and Charles Darwin, as
opposed to the transcendentalist tradition of Plato, Immanuel Kant, and John
Rawls.
If Wilson's project for a
Darwinian unification of knowledge is to succeed, it must revive that
Aristotelian tradition of natural philosophy that includes Thomas Aquinas, Hume,
and Adam Smith. Darwin understood himself as part of that intellectual
tradition, particularly in adopting ideas from Hume and Smith about the natural
moral sentiments. Even Darwin’s fundamental idea of the evolutionary
emergence of life as an unintended order was derived from Smith and other
Scottish philosophers.
Recently, evolutionary
moral psychologists like Jonathan Haidt have recognized that they are reviving
the empiricist moral philosophy of Aristotle and Hume. Some contemporary philosophers have embraced
"experimental philosophy" as a way of putting their ideas to the test
of empirical scientific research. A few political scientists have begun
to argue that their science needs to become a biopolitical science of political
animals. All of this contributes to a modern
renewal of the ancient quest for a philosophical science of nature through a
Darwinian natural philosophy.
We must wonder, however,
whether such a Darwinian natural philosophy can be defended against the many
criticisms that it faces. Two of the
most prominent criticisms are the charges of reductionism and nihilism.
Wilson’s reductionism is
suggested by his statement in Consilience about reducing all knowledge
to physics: "all tangible phenomena, from the birth of stars to the working
of social institutions, are based on material processes that are ultimately
reducible, however long and tortuous the sequences, to the laws of physics.”
This strong reductionism is so implausible that even Wilson cannot consistently
embrace it. In most of Consilience, he actually rejected
"physics envy," and he insisted that biologists must
"invariably encounter emergence, the appearance of complex phenomena not
predictable from the basic elements and processes alone.” He identified
human beings as “emergent animals” who have capacities that are constrained,
but not specifically determined by the laws of physics. In The Social Conquest of Earth,
Wilson never argues for reducing everything to the laws of physics, and he
implicitly endorses the idea of the irreducibly emergent traits of life.
Biologists recognize
emergent phenomena as those complex wholes with properties that we could not
explain or predict from our knowledge of the parts. The emergence of novelty occurs throughout
the evolution of the universe. Passing
through levels of complexity, new properties emerge at higher levels that are
not fully reducible to the lower levels.
When chemicals in the early universe formed the first living cells, that
was emergence. When the first multicellar
organism arose, that was emergence. When
the human mind arose from the evolution of the primate brain passing over a
critical threshold of size and complexity (particularly, in the prefrontal
cortex), that was emergence. Although
the human mind is constrained by the laws of physics and chemistry, we cannot
fully explain or precisely predict the workings of that mind through the laws
of physics and chemistry.
One ground for emergent
complexity in Wilson's science is genetic plasticity. Wilson is often accused
of genetic determinism, even though he has repeatedly affirmed genetic
plasticity as allowing for individual and cultural variation. He repeats
that idea in Social Conquest in explaining gene-culture coevolution: there
can be plasticity in the expression of genes that allows for a wide but still
constrained flexibility in response to the cultural and individual
contingencies of life. Our human genetic
nature constrains but does not determine our cultural traditions and individual
judgments.
How does the coevolution
of genes, culture, and judgment explain human morality and politics? Some critics of Wilson’s project worry that
any evolutionary account of morality and politics must deny that there can be
any objective or fixed standards of right and wrong, which is nihilism.
Is Darwinism
nihilism? If you are a Platonist,
yes. If you are not a Platonist, no.
Most Platonists today are
disappointed Platonists—people with
Platonic expectations that are unfulfilled, because they accept Darwinian
evolution as true, and therefore since all living forms have evolved, they
cannot be eternal in conforming to Plato’s intelligible realm of eternal
Ideas. If everything has evolved, this
must include moral and political order, and thus there is no eternally unchanging
Idea of the Good by which we can see absolute standards of right and
wrong. Consequently, there are no moral
absolutes, and we must accept moral relativism or nihilism. Darwinism is “true but deadly” (as Friedrich
Nietzsche said). And thus these disappointed
Platonists become nihilists.
But if you do not have
Platonic expectations, you will not be disappointed by the Darwinian conclusion
that everything has evolved, and therefore human beings have evolved. Without the Platonic assumption that morality
must be grounded in a moral cosmology,
you will be satisfied with a Darwinian explanation of morality as grounded in a
moral anthropology. Even if morality has no eternal grounding in
a cosmic God, a cosmic Nature, or a cosmic Reason, human morality still has an evolutionary grounding in human
nature, human culture, and human judgment. You can say, with Leo Strauss, that “however
indifferent to moral distinctions the cosmic order may be thought to be, human
nature, as distinguished from nature in general, may very well be the basis of
such distinctions.” And thus in contrast
to the disappointed Platonists, the satisfied Darwinians are not nihilists.
Satisfied Darwinians like
Wilson see at least four mechanisms for the evolution of social cooperation and
human morality: kin selection (cooperating with relatives), direct reciprocity
(tit-for-tat exchanges), indirect reciprocity (having a good or bad
reputation), and multilevel selection (individual selection and group
selection).
The most controversial
part of Wilson’s new book is that while he had previously embraced kin
selection theory, he now argues against it.
Kin selection is the idea that animals have evolved to serve not only their
personal fitness (the number of their surviving offspring) but also their
inclusive fitness (including the fitness of their collateral relatives), and
consequently animals tend to be altruistic towards closely related kin with
whom they share genes. Wilson argues
that as long as multilevel natural selection (individual or group selection, or
both) works generally to explain social evolution, there is no need for a
theory of kin selection.
But multilevel selection
theory is not an alternative to kin selection theory; rather, they are
complimentary to one another. Kin
selection cannot be the whole story, because we need to explain how unrelated
individuals can cooperate. But kin
selection must be part of the story, because we need to explain the tendency
for individuals to be more cooperative with close relatives than with distant
relatives or strangers. This idea was
developed by Aristotle: the natural
sociality of animals originates as an extension of parental care and
affiliation to ever wider groups.
Aristotle also saw that this natural sociality reached its peak among
the social insects and human beings, and thus again Aristotle anticipated
Wilson.
In Sociobiology, Wilson
identified four pinnacles of social evolution:
the colonial invertebrates (such as the corals, the Portuguese
man-of-war, and sponges), the eusocial insects (ants, bees, wasps, and
termites), nonhuman mammals, and humans. Although this sequence seems to
move from more primitive to more complex forms of life, it also moves from more
cohesive or cooperative societies to more discordant or competitive
societies. Colonial invertebrates can be seen as "perfect
societies," because colonies consist of genetically identical individuals,
and consequently they show absolutely altruistic cooperation. But with
sexually reproducing organisms, no two individuals are genetically identical,
which creates conflicts of interest even among related individuals.
In Social Conquest,
Wilson moves from four pinnacles of social evolution to two. He identifies
two paths to the social conquest of the earth--the insect path and the human
path. The social insects rule the invertebrate land environment. Humans rule the vertebrate land
environment. Like the social insects, humans are "eusocial" in
the technical sense that multiple generations of individuals live together,
caring for dependent offspring and cooperating in a social division of
labor. While the social insects organize their colonies largely through
pure instinct, with the insect queen producing robotic offspring guided by
instinct, humans must organize the cooperation of individuals through personal
relationships based on social intelligence, which requires navigating through a
tense social network balanced between the selfish interests of individuals and
the social interests of groups. Wilson explains this tense balance in
human social life between selfishness and sociality as showing the
countervailing evolutionary forces of individual selection and group selection.
The unsteady balance between
the individual and the group in human societies constitutes what Wilson
identifies as the "iron rule" of social and moral evolution:
"Selfish individuals beat altruistic individuals, while groups of
altruists beat groups of selfish individuals. The victory can never be
complete; the balance of selection pressures cannot move to either
extreme. If individual selection were to dominate, societies would
dissolve. If group selection were to dominate, human groups would come to
resemble ant colonies.” So if we ask whether human beings are innately
good or innately evil, we should answer that they are both. And for that
reason, "human beings and their social orders are intrinsically
imperfectible.” Here is the scientific basis for the tragic realism of
evolutionary ethics.
The ultimate mechanisms
of moral evolution are enforced through the proximate mechanisms of moral
emotions. For example, Wilson identifies
the human sense of honor as crucial for moral experience. This sense of honor includes the moral
emotions of indignation and resentment in response to injustice. This
sense of injustice might express what Leo Strauss called "those simple
experiences regarding right and wrong which are at the bottom of the
philosophic contention that there is a natural right." It is this that allows us to derive rights
from wrongs: our moral history is a history of resistance to injustice from
which we derive standards of fair treatment. But if those “simple experiences regarding right and wrong” are the
purely human experiences of an animal species shaped by evolutionary history,
and if that evolved human species is enduring but not eternal, do those
experiences support the philosophic claim that there is a natural right? The Darwinian natural philosopher says yes.
Prof. Arnhart,
ReplyDeleteWhat an excellent review. I find your arguments here, as always, compelling.
A long question:
Even if our evolved human nature can be the basis for a normative ethics, are there not still tensions between the “is” and the “ought?” And if so, what are the implications?
I am thinking primarily of the human desires on your list in DNR numbered 8 (justice) and 19 (religion).
To take the latter first, if we have a natural desire for religion, then this cannot be satisfied by human reason alone- i.e. a philosophical, but skeptical openness to the divine is at best half way there.
To take the issue discussed in the second half of this post - justice - next, a virtue ethics that is based on our human nature, is, as you imply, admittedly narrower than a “cosmic” morality (but still not the standard, modern, happy-go-lucky nihilisms of one form or another that abound). However, when we consider not petty theft, nor rude behavior, but truly ghastly and heinous crimes, our natural moral sentiments seem to desire a cosmic morality, or at least something closer to it. That is, the natural right arguments that support the “ought,” don’t seem commensurate with our sense of the injustice. In yet other words, the idea that the deviant perpetrator is simply unhappy, or not “flourishing” (the reverse side of the coin of virtue being happiness) does not seem to match our level of moral disdain and condemnation.
It would seem, then, that it is our evolved human nature itself that almost assuredly explains the presence of these “disappointed Platonists” in our midst.
While neither case above disproves nor even really undermines the strength of the general argument, they do lead to my question about a tension between our human nature, fully and rightly understood (as in your extended arguments), and the only “ought” that can be supplied by human reason. If so, then this would seem to point to a tension or lack of full compatibility between your last desire (in DNR: intellectual understanding) and the other 19, no?
-Wbond
I attempt to answer my own question here: http://wbonds.blogspot.com/2013/11/is-examined-life-worth-living.html
ReplyDelete