Thursday, January 04, 2024

Roger D. Masters, 1933-2023: Natural Right and Biology



Roger D. Masters died in Hanover, New Hampshire, on June 22, 2023.  He was a longtime Professor of Government at Dartmouth College.  He was the man who first stimulated my thinking about how evolutionary biology might be applied to political philosophy--and particularly, how it might solve what Leo Strauss called "the problem of natural right."

He was born in Boston in 1933.  He graduated from Harvard University in 1955.  He completed two years of military service.  Then he earned his Ph.D. from the University of Chicago in 1961, studying under Leo Strauss, who supervised his dissertation on Jean-Jacques Rousseau.  After teaching for five years in the Political Science Department at Yale University, he began his position at Dartmouth in 1967.  He served as Chair of the Executive Committee of the Gruter Institute for Law and Behavioral Research.  He was one of the founders of the Association for Politics and the Life Sciences.

With the publication of his book The Political Philosophy of Rousseau (Princeton University Press, 1968), he became one of the preeminent interpreters of Rousseau.  He published translations of Rousseau.  With Christopher Kelly, he edited The Collected Writings of Rousseau.  He also wrote many articles and books on other political philosophers, including Aristotle and Niccolo Machiavelli.

He is best known for arguing that modern evolutionary biology of human nature can illuminate some of the fundamental debates in political philosophy.  One can see that in his books The Nature of Politics (1989), and Beyond Relativism: Science and Human Values (1993).

Towards the end of this life, he studied the possible effects of toxic lead on the development of the brain in ways that might promote a tendency to violence.

Roger's profound influence on me began in 1978 when I heard him present a paper on "Classical Political Philosophy and Contemporary Biology" at the meetings of the Conference for the Study of Political Thought in Chicago.  He argued that modern evolutionary biology could support Aristotle's conception of natural right.  I was fascinated.  In 1998, my book Darwinian Natural Right was in a way an elaboration of his idea.

Roger invited me to meetings of the Gruter Institute.  We were together at many gatherings of the Association for Politics and the Life Sciences.  And in 1996, I participated in a NEH/NSF Summer Institute at Dartmouth College that he directed on "Biology and Human Nature."

I have written about Roger on this blog.  My fullest account of Roger's thinking was my book chapter--"Roger Masters: Natural Right and Biology"--for Leo Strauss, the Straussians, and the American Regime (1999),  edited by Kenneth Deutsch and John Murley.

Here are four paragraphs from the beginning and ending of that piece.

As compared with other students of Leo Strauss who became prominent political scientists, the intellectual career of Roger Masters seems strange.  As a graduate student at the University of Chicago, Masters wrote his dissertation on Jean-Jacques Rousseau under Strauss's supervision.  He then established his scholar reputation in the 1960s through his writings on Rousseau's political philosophy.  At that point, it appeared that Masters would follow the same path taken by many of Strauss's students who have devoted their lives to writing meticulous commentaries on the classic texts of political philosophy.  

But after publishing his book on Rousseau in 1968, Masters began to write about evolutionary biology.  For example, he suggested that Rousseau's account of man in the original state of nature should be compared with recent studies of orangutans as evolutionary ancestors of human beings; and he argued that Aristotle's claim that human beings are by nature political animals was confirmed by recent sociobiological theories of human evolution and animal sociality.  Most recently, he has explained Machiavelli's concept of political leadership as rooted in a natural tendency to dominance hierarchies that human beings share with other primates.  The history of political philosophy is largely a debate about human nature.  And Masters believes that debate can be clarified, if not even resolved, by appealing to Darwinian theories of human nature.  To many of Strauss's students, such ideas seem ridiculously perverse.  Yet a few Straussians have been persuaded by Masters that this turn to Darwinian biology is essential for solving what Strauss called "the problem of natural right."

In his effort to root the idea of natural right in modern natural science, and thus solve what Strauss believed was the fundamental problem of natural right--that science seems to have refuted the teleological conception of nature--Masters challenges the dichotomies that have traditionally separated the humanistic study of ethics from the scientific study of nature.  There is no absolute gap between mechanism and teleology if a full explanation of living beings requires accounting for formal and final causes as well as material and efficient causes.  There is no absolute gap between is and ought if human morality is founded on a natural moral sense.  There is no absolute gap between nature and freedom if human freedom expresses a natural human capacity for deliberate choice.  and there is no absolute gap between nature and nurture if habituation and learning fulfill the natural propensities of human beings.  If Masters is right in these claims, then the science of the human good is part of the science of human nature.

Although I find the arguments of Masters largely persuasive, I suspect that many readers will disagree.  As Strauss indicated, most contemporary scholars have responded to the apparent refutation of ancient naturalism by modern natural science in one of two ways--reductionism or dualism.  The reductionists will agree with Masters that moral feelings are governed by the emotional control centers of the brain, but they will conclude from this that belief in the objectivity of morality is only a useful illusion.  The dualists, including many of the students of Strauss, will insist that human biology is irrelevant to human ethics and politics, because human beings as rational beings differ in kind and not just in degree from all other animals, and for that reason Darwin's evolutionary account of human morality and intellect is wrong.  Yet for those of us who regard both of these opposing positions as inadequate, the alternative o0ffered by Masters in his attempt to solve the problem of natural right is one of the most exciting intellectual projects of our time.

I regret that I had little contact with Roger in the last years of his life.  I wish that I had told him how much I had benefited from our philosophic friendship.

I will remember him.

6 comments:

Les Brunswick said...

My impression is that the leading rival to this view is the idea that human beings originally lived a solitary, asocial existence, as claimed by thinkers Hobbes, Rousseau, Hegel, and Nietzsche.

There are many objections to this view, but one very strong one is that human beings as a biological species simply lack the ability to survive if not living in societies. Others include that our closest primate relatives are social, and the many observed social psychological characteristics that human beings have, many from birth or a young age, including motivations, cognitive abilities, and unlearned behavior patterns.

As far as I can tell, the writers who hold the original asocial existence doctrine simply ignore these various arguments, and just go on dogmatically claiming it.

Larry Arnhart said...
This comment has been removed by the author.
Larry Arnhart said...

I have written a post (Sept. 6, 2018) on some evidence in some primates for Rousseau's pure state of nature as "solitary but not asocial."

W. Bond said...

As a related aside, In NRH Chapter 3 Strauss describes how a certain understanding of virtue is possible under the pre-Socratic philosophic understanding -- conventionalism -- which he sees as continuing to develop as Epicureanism and as comes down to us in Lucretius.

In Chapter 4 (and elsewhere) he indicates that Socrates takes a famous turn that has not just an arbitrary new focus, but an epistemologic basis, "a new approach to the understanding of all things." Strauss seems to suggest that Socratic rationalism anticipates not just the 20th c. nihilistic cul-de-sacs of social science positivism and historicism, but even current issues in the philosophy of science (although being careful, he never states things so broadly).

Aristotle, despite his famous differences with Plato, is grouped, of course, as Socratic.

In Strauss' brief but fascinating treatment of Cicero and his friend Atticus on pp 154-156 we see him suggesting that there may be more agreement about the question of natural right between a Socratic and an Epicurean than would appear on the surface.

I'll end this rambling about NRH with three questions, if you have time:

1. Is there any meaningful difference in your view between an Aristotlean approach to natural science e.g in biology, etc. (the spirit of it, if you'll allow that -- "Aristotle would have been the first to look through the telescope" etc.) vs. an "Epicurean" approach? Are not modern mathematical experimental methods, as well as observational methods, compatible with both?
2. Does the answer to #1 have any bearing on natural right in your full formulation? Is the "Arnhart Natural Right" Epicurean or Aristotlean or is there no difference? Is Aristotle grouped above incorrectly due to his teacher?
3. Is there in fact a Socratic rationalism, a method that anticipates current issues in the philosophy/science, yet to be fully realized generally, or does it just anticipate the tendency towards bad science, "scientism," simplistic reductionism, etc. and indeed careful philosophy/science is "Socratic" without calling itself that, or is there nothing to this Straussian claim and project?

Thanks!

--WBond

Larry Arnhart said...

I will offer only a partial answer to your questions.

Strauss begins NRH by saying that "natural right in its classic form is connected with a teleological view of the universe" that "would seem to have been destroyed by modern natural science." And Aristotle agrees that natural right depends on a teleological conception of the universe (7-8).

But much of what Strauss says in NRH denies this. This also contradicts what Strauss says in The City of Man (21) about how Aristotle's "quest for the best political order" does not depend on his cosmology.

Strauss recognizes "the most terrible truth" of Lucretian evolution (Liberalism, Ancient & Modern, 135).

He also suggests that the teleology required for natural right does not have to be a cosmic or theological teleology, but rather an immanent teleology of the natural human desires and inclinations that would be supported by Epicurean and Lucretian science and perhaps Cicero's Academic skepticism (94-95, 154-55).

Although Plato often seems to endorse a cosmic/theological teleology (Timaeus), Plato's Socrates often suggests that there can be a purely human teleology of the natural desires. I wrote about that some years ago in comments on Catherine Zuckert's Plato's Philosophers.

W. Bond said...

Thank you for the very thorough, rich, and generous reply!

And, although, it's a broad -- and perhaps unfair -- part of the questions posed, it seems to me that one could make an argument that your approach to immanent teleology in biology, and to a non-reductionist biology in general, is consistent with "noetic heterogeneity," even if that claim is not a full analysis of the question regarding Socratic method.