On September 16 (Friday), I will be presenting a paper at the 2022 Convention of the American Political Science Association in Montreal. The title of the paper is "The Biopolitical Science of Lockean Liberal Punishment." This will be part of a panel on "Emotions and Politics," meeting in the Westin Hotel, third floor, in the St.-Suplice room, 2:00-3:30 pm.
Here is the concluding section of my paper:
For political science to
become a biopolitical science, political theory would have to become a
biopolitical theory by applying biological science to the reasoning of
political theorists. As an illustration
of how this could be done, I have applied evolutionary biology to John Locke’s theory
of how the natural human propensity to punish violations of the law of nature
enforces the liberal principle that all human beings are by nature equally free. I have summarized how Locke understood the
emergence of forcible punishment and reputational punishment in the state of
nature, the popular consent to forcible punishment by government, and the
popular punishment of despotic government.
From this Lockean theory of liberal punishment, I have generated five
testable predictions, and I have argued that they can be largely confirmed by
evolutionary anthropology.
First, evolutionary anthropology can show how in the
evolutionary state of nature of hunter-gatherer bands, people enforced a
cooperative social order by punishing those individuals who violated those informal
norms of good conduct that Locke identified as the law of nature.
Second, in the debate among evolutionary anthropologists as
to whether the state of nature in the foraging era was a Hobbesian state of war
or a Rousseauian state of peace, we can see that Locke was closer to the truth
than either Hobbes or Rousseau, because while the foraging life can be
generally peaceful, it easily becomes violent; and therefore people will choose
to establish governmental institutions for punishment that pacify society.
Third, as Locke predicted, evolutionary moral anthropology
and social neuroscience have shown that there are some universal norms of good
conduct enforced by forcible and reputational punishment.
Fourth, we have seen that the archaeological and
anthropological studies of the earliest history of government confirm what
Locke learned from Acosta and Sagard about popular council democracy being one
of the earliest forms of government, in which people punish those individuals
who try to coercively dominate others, thus enforcing the liberal idea that
every adult individual is equally free and independent.
Finally, in support of Locke’s prediction that people will punish
despotic government by rebelling against it, we have seen that the evolutionary
history of government shows a natural human propensity to punish despotic
rulers through violent and nonviolent resistance, although these revolutionary
movements are not always successful.
This biopolitical science of Lockean liberal punishment
illustrates how political philosophy can become a biological science of human political
life. A biopolitical philosophy can become
part of a biopolitical science that employs evolutionary thinking as a way of
unifying knowledge across all the disciplines of the natural sciences, the
social sciences, and the humanities in studying the evolved nature of human
beings as political animals. Through
such a biopolitical science, we can better understand how these human political
animals find their home in the order of living nature.
No comments:
Post a Comment